ABSTRACT
Title of Dissertation:
A PECULIAR FAITH:
NAVIGATING ROUSSEAU’S ROAD TO
DEMOCRATIC VIRTUE
Joshua Karant, Ph.D., 2004
Dissertation Directed By:
Professor Benjamin R. Barber, Department of
Government and Politics
The relationship between religion and politics poses a pressing—and
oftentimes combustible—problem for contemporary democracies. The terror of
September 11
th
, global suicide bombings, and attacks on America’s abortion clinics
illustrate the imminent dangers of political protest driven by fanatical faith. But
authors such as Machiavelli, Tocqueville and, more recently, William Galston and
Manning Marable suggest something different. Religion, they argue, cultivates virtue
amongst citizens and must be incorporated into the pluralist fold.
These dissonant conclusions underscore the difficulty of navigating the
tension between spiritual and secular values. Does religion subvert liberal democratic
principles of neutrality and equality under law, or does it offer an essential foundation
for secular virtue? If religion provides a moral compass compatible with democracy,
do religious systems inevitably undermine open, participatory politics? If so, how
might we cultivate political virtue without compromising strong citizenship?
For Jean-Jacques Rousseau, the answer lies in Civil Religion, a model
wherein spiritual virtue and religious piety uphold political liberty and strong
citizenship. Does Rousseau ask too much? Does he attempt to marry irreconcilable
partners, or is his vision practicable and persuasive? Adopting the divisive
relationship between religion and politics as its central concern,
A Peculiar Faith
examines Rousseau’s secular theology as a means of confronting this contentious and
still-relevant dilemma.
A PECULIAR FAITH:
NAVIGATING ROUSSEAU’S ROAD TO DEMOCRATIC VIRTUE
By
Joshua Karant
Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the
University of Maryland, College Park, in partial fulfillment
of the requirements for the degree of
Doctor of Philosophy
2004
Advisory Committee:
Professor Benjamin R. Barber, Chair
Professor Charles E. Butterworth
Professor William A. Galston
Professor James E. Miller
Professor Vladimir Tismaneanu
© Cop yright by
Joshua Karant
2004
ii
Dedication
To Luka and Jan
.
iii
Acknowledgements
The sentences you are about to read are mine, but they would not have been
written without the guidance and support of colleagues, friends and family. First and
foremost, I owe tremendous gratitude to Benjamin R. Barber. I first met Dr. Barber
in a Rousseau seminar at Rutgers University. When he accepted an offer to join the
faculty at the University of Maryland, he graciously suggested that I accompany him.
What, at the time, seemed a potentially brash gamble proved, in hindsight, to be the
most significant decision of my academic career. I cannot thank Barber enough for
his contributions to my personal and professional development, his generosity in
funding my interests and supporting me at every turn, and his role as an educator,
mentor and friend. I am as grateful for his warmth, insight, and encouragement, as I
am for the passion with which he challenged, provoked, confronted and tested me.
The work at hand is a testament to, and reflection of, our relationship.
If Barber was my fountainhead, several prepared me for his tutelage. My path
to political theory began at Pomona College, and the blame (as it were) rests largely
on the shoulders of John Seery. To this day, Seery remains a gadfly, a confidant, a
compatriot, and one of the most influential professors with whom I have had the
pleasure of studying. The same holds true for James Miller and Richard Shusterman.
I happened across Miller’s
Passion of Michel Foucault
while living in Oahu, and
made the fruitful pilgrimage to New York to work with him at the New School. His
commitment to my intellectual growth never wavered (even when I did), and I was
fortunate to have benefited from his affection, erudition, scholarly rigor, and utter
iv
lack of artifice. He taught me how to approach texts critically but independently,
with a disciplined eye for precision that never sacrificed creativity. Shusterman
proved a particularly empathetic ally as well. Sensitive to my interests, strengths and
weaknesses alike, he treated me as an equal and exposed me to an art of life towards
which I continue to humbly, and hopefully, aspire.
It is barely possible to list every person who influenced and assisted me
during my academic training, but several others warrant especial acknowledgment.
Wilson Carey McWilliams’ wisdom and warmth provided great inspiration, solace,
and guidance both during and well beyond my tenure at Rutgers. And at the
University of Maryland, I was fortunate to have worked with William Galston and
Vladimir Tismaneanu. Galston’s decency, attentiveness, sound judgment, and
remarkably fluid mind made the move to College Park wholly worthwhile.
Tismaneanu likewise graced me with his generous spirit, critical acuity, and
wonderfully provocative reading of Rousseau. Along with the accomplished and
estimable Charles Butterworth, and Barber and Miller, they formed a committee
invaluable in realizing and honing the vision that guided this work.
I am also grateful for the feedback and critique I received from friends and
colleagues alike, including Derek Barker, Isabelle V. Barker, Sharon E. Goldman,
Bryan McGraw, Philip Spivey, and Matthew Voorhees. Charles Kim also merits
special recognition. Kim took significant time from his own research on Korean
history to provide as close, thoughtful and thorough a reading of early drafts as any I
received.
v
In addition, this work would not have been possible without support from the
Democracy Collaborative. The Collaborative went above and beyond the call of duty
in ensuring my sustained and generous funding as a Research Fellow, providing the
framework and autonomy to pursue my own scholarly interests while simultaneously
realizing projects on global citizenship and civic education.
Finally, these acknowledgments would be woefully incomplete without a
recognition of Janet Austin. Harboring a graduate student is no mean feat,
particularly in my case. At times I would have been hard-pressed to find my way out
of a paper bag, let alone write a coherent work. Yet throughout it all, Janet provided
not merely encouragement and affection, but also grounding, focus, strength, and the
wellsprings of her tremendous organizational skills. When I drifted off into sermons
on the Pelagian heresy, she reminded me of the task at hand; when I suggested fleeing
to Paris, she kept me at my computer in Brooklyn, plugging ahead; and whenever the
goal seemed beyond my capacities, she insisted otherwise. It is with love and
admiration that I dedicate
A Peculiar Faith
to her.
Brooklyn, New York
November 8, 2004
vi
Table of Contents
Dedication ..................................................................................................................... ii
Acknowledgements...................................................................................................... iii
Table of Contents ......................................................................................................... vi
Note on Translation..................................................................................................... vii
List of Abbreviations ................................................................................................. viii
Introduction................................................................................................................... 1
Chapter 1: Strained Relations ..................................................................................... 10
Chapter 2: The Virtue of Paradox ............................................................................... 35
Chapter 3: A Claim of Innocence ............................................................................... 86
Chapter 4: The Reluctant Recluse............................................................................ 150
Chapter 5: Church and State ..................................................................................... 200
Chapter 6: The Road to Vincennes ........................................................................... 247
Bibliography ............................................................................................................. 269
vii
Note on Translation
Rather than recreating the wheel, and for the sake of consistency, translations
of Rousseau’s works are largely based upon the wonderful University Press of New
England series,
The Collected Writings of Rousseau
. I have only occasionally found
need to make corrections (based upon the Pléiade edition), or draw attention to
nuances particular to the French language. All other translations are mine, unless
noted.
viii
List of Abbreviations
In French
OC
Oeuvres complètes, tomes 1-5
. Bernard Gagnebin and Marcel Raymond, eds.
(Paris: Éditions Gallimard/Bibliothèque de la Pléiade, 1959-1995).
CC
Correspondance complète de Jean-Jacques Rousseau
, R.A. Leigh, ed.
(Genève: Institut et Museé Voltaire, 1965— )
In Translation
CW
The Collected Writings of Rousseau, Vols. 1-10
. Roger D. Masters and
Christopher Kelly, eds. (Hanover, NH: University Press of New England,
1990-2004).
E
Emile, or On Education
, Allan Bloom, tr. (New York: Basic Books, 1979).
1
Introduction
Rousseau touched the hearts of a great many people who felt the author spoke
directly to them.
1
Yet the reputation of his works is dogged by their perceived
contradictions. Rousseau vehemently rejected such charges, even as he admitted to
the paradoxical nature of his thought. If the temperamental author had his way,
readers would surely follow the fictional Frenchman’s lead in his
Dialogues
and
recognize his
oeuvres
as “things that were profoundly thought out, forming a coherent
system which might not be true but which offered nothing contradictory.”
2
Rousseau’s insistent claims notwithstanding, his writings strike inharmonious chords.
Of these, perhaps none rings more awkwardly than his simultaneous embrace of
religiosity and secularism.
Writing as if attuned to the means of salvation, Rousseau incorporated both
Christian and Pagan traditions within a vision of strong democratic citizenship and
corporeal improvement. How did these competing influences unfold as a model of
practicable reform? Was their synthesis compelling? Or even coherent? What might
we make of Rousseau’s religious conviction, and its relation to civic harmony and
political virtue? And for a thinker so obviously concerned with secular affairs, why
was religion necessary to his thought?
1
See: Robert Darnton, “Readers Respond to Rousseau: The Fabrication of Romantic Sensitivity,” in
The Great Cat Massacre and Other Episodes in French Cultural History
. (New York: Basic Books,
1983).
2
In claiming both that his works “offered nothing contradictory” and that paradox was “necessary” to
his thought, Rousseau forced a crucial distinction between paradox and inconsistency discussed in
Chapter 2 above.
Dialogues
. CW I.209; OC I.930.
2
Because Rousseau’s writings are rife with paradoxes and antinomies, answers
do not come easily. Indeed, his efforts have conspicuously divided audiences. In
Rousseau’s own age, Frederick the Great believed that the Genevan’s moral rigor was
matched only by his saint-like self-castigation.
3
Yet the Archduke Christophe de
Beaumont derided him as a dangerous heretic, the living epitome of Saint Paul’s
prophecy of “perilous days” destined to cloud mankind’s future.
4
To most—his
friends, foes, and intellectual peers alike—Rousseau was a rabble-rouser cut of
Diogenes the Cynic’s abrasive cloth. Yet to himself, he was one of the last few true
Christians, believers who followed the gospel of Christ rather than the Church’s
dictates.
Was Jean-Jacques pious or profane, a disciple of Jesus or a radical Pagan
upstart? Evidence suggests that each of these descriptions bears some measure of
truth. Deeply engaged with the corporeal world as critic and reformer, he drew a
paradoxical faith in the capacity for human redemption from a heterodox assumption
of man’s natural goodness. Applying virulent social criticism to an optimistic vision
of political reform, he rose to fame as a demonstrative recluse—a thinker ill-at-ease in
the society to whose improvement he was so deeply committed. Such engagement
reflects wholly secular concerns, yet Rousseau’s work also betrayed strong
religiosity. His faith in human innocence rested upon a self-professed love of divine
order and the natural world of God’s creation. From his very first
Discourse
, to the
Vicar’s
Profession
, to the final
Reveries
, Rousseau urged us to follow the principles
3
For a detailed discussion of Frederick’s claim, see Chapter 4 below.
4
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.3. Beaumont’s Biblical reference is to 2
Timothy
3:1-4, 8.
3
of virtue “engraved in all hearts” and revealed through the God-given conscience
from which socialized man had alienated himself.
One of his epoch’s most virulent anti-Clericalists, Rousseau nonetheless
embraced religion as a necessary foundation for individual and collective
improvement. Yet his vision of piety rested upon a Pelagian heresy, a claim of
ontological innocence that was itself colored by a profound mistrust of human
society. A self-designated recluse, he expressed personal distaste for social
obligation, duty and convention. A champion of cohesive communities, he found
peace only in solitude, alone amongst nature while lost in his passionate reveries.
Perhaps the greatest social critic of his age, he staked his career—and following his
motto,
5
his very life—on a mission of public service: pursuing the truth and revealing
it to his peers. Yet this secular calling was itself the fruit borne of a spiritual
conversion, an epiphany that changed his life on the road to Vincennes.
Such are the beds of Rousseau’s making, and the conspicuously strange
bedfellows he conjured. Taken together, his skepticism of men (as social creatures
infected with amour-propre) and faith in man (
en générale
, as creations of God
endowed with conscience) appear to be incompatible. Rousseau’s sunny view of
human nature seems ill-fitted with his belief in Divine order and an afterlife, two
concepts traditionally used to literally instill the fear of God in the descendents of
Adam. His acute distrust of formal religion only complicates matters. If man is
good and religion is necessary, yet men have grown as wicked and corrupt as
religious institutions, can we honestly hope for improvement? What concrete lesson
5
Namely,
Vitam impendere vero
(
Dedicate life to truth
). For a more thorough examination of
Rousseau’s motto see Chapter 2 below.
4
might we draw from these inchoate conclusions? Can such a dissonant theory
materialize in practice?
Again, Rousseau’s readers harbored strong doubts. Even those who
appreciated his work have wished aloud that the Genevan abandon his dialectic
approach for a more singular methodology and agenda. If only Rousseau had chosen
a more righteous path unencumbered by earthly affairs, perhaps he would have
survived the Enlightenment as one of the world’s great martyrs, a figure deified
without irony or scorn. Infighting with the
philosophes
, repentant success,
hypersensitivity over his reputation and legacy, and eventual exile only heightened
his discomfort and fueled his critics; yet he never relinquished his burdensome
commitment to corporeal reform.
Rousseau was, after all, equally enamored with spiritual and secular
improvement. To abandon one would have been to destroy the provocative dialectic
that makes his thought so compelling. Had he convincingly renounced his ties to the
world, the questions that now confront us would be irrelevant. He would not have
struggled to envision religious associations compatible with liberal democratic
principles of tolerance, equality and strong citizenship. He would not, in other words,
have formulated his theory of Civil Religion.
Civil Religion is a nexus of Rousseau’s earthly and otherworldly concerns.
One of his most widely-disparaged writings, this attempt to found a “purely civil
faith” (a term which itself testifies to his confluence of spiritual and secular values)
marked a culminating point in Rousseau’s life-consuming quest to foster religious
and political reform. In it, we find an author struggling to apply his faith to practice,
5
to reconcile his dour view of the world as it
was
with his dream of society as it
should
be
.
6
In the end, was he successful? Were his apparently competing influences and
aims irreconcilable? Or does Rousseau offer a powerful lens through which to
reconsider the relationship between religion and politics?
* * * * *
Readers may yet ask, why another book about Rousseau? Although the topic
of his religiosity has been long-studied, I believe it could be
better
studied. After all,
the most thorough and widely-acclaimed writings are both aged and unavailable in
English: P.-M. Masson and William Cuendet wrote nearly one century ago, while
comparable works from renowned scholars such as Robert Dérathe and Pierre
Burgelin date from the middle of the twentieth-century.
7
To be fair, contemporary authors have expanded upon these pioneering
efforts. James Miller and Helena Rosenblatt discussed Rousseau’s relationship to
Protestantism in illuminating the significance of his Swiss heritage.
8
In
Not By
Reason Alone
, Joshua Mitchell explored the influence of Christian and Protestant
6
This is, of course, a reference to
The Social Contract
’s opening lines: “I want to inquire whether there
can be a legitimate and reliable rule of administration in the civil order, taking men as they
are
and
laws as they
can be
.” As we will see, this dialectic between realism and idealism is central to
Rousseau’s religious and political thought alike.
The Social Contract
. CW IV.131; OC III.351. (My
emphasis.)
7
See: Pierre-Maurice Masson,
La Religion de J. J. Rousseau
, Vols. I-III. (Paris: Librairie Hachette,
1916); William Cuendet,
La Philosophie religieuse de Jean-Jacques Rousseau et ses sources
. (Geneva:
A. Jullien, 1913); Robert Dérathe,
Le rationalisme de Jean-Jacques Rousseau
. (Paris: Presses
Universitaires de France, 1948); Pierre Burgelin,
Jean-Jacques Rousseau et la religion de Genève
.
(Geneva: Éditions Labor et Fides, 1962).
8
See: James Miller,
Rousseau: Dreamer of Democracy
. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1984);
Helena Rosenblatt,
Rousseau and Geneva: From the First discourse to the Social Contract
,
1749-
1762
. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997).
6
authors upon his thought.
9
Ann Hartle’s eloquent work,
The Modern Self in
Rousseau’s Confessions
,
10
analyzed the Augustinian elements within his model of
self-discovery, a connection likewise detailed by Christopher Brooke
11
and
Christopher Kelly.
12
Victor Gourevitch
13
drew attention to Rousseau’s providential
description of “nature,” while Ronald Grimsley
14
expounded upon his Biblical
concept of redemption. And Patrick Riley’s well-documented
The General Will
Before Rousseau
illustrated the Malebranchian influence upon his concept of
voluntarism, while charting the general will’s movement from a divine to a civic
emphasis.
15
Despite the breadth and depth of such scholarship, however, rarely is
Rousseau’s religion considered as a keystone to his political vision, and a crucial
linkage which unites his entire
oeuvres
.
16
Quite the contrary, far more effort has been
9
Mitchell goes so far as to claim that “Rousseau and Luther embark on identical projects” of social
criticism. Joshua Mitchell,
Not By Reason Alone: Religion, History and Identity in Early Modern
Political Thought
. (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1993).
10
See: Ann Hartle,
The Modern Self in Rousseau’s Confessions: A Reply to Saint Augustine
. (Notre
Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983).
11
Christopher Brooke, “Rousseau’s Political Philosophy: Stoic and Augustinian Origins,” in Patrick
Riley, ed.,
The Cambridge Companion to Rousseau
. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).
12
Christopher Kelly,
Rousseau’s Exemplary Life: The “Confessions” as Political Philosophy
. (Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press, 1987).
13
Victor Gourevitch, “The Religious Thought,” in Riley.
14
Ronald Grimsley,
Rousseau and the Religious Quest
. (London: Oxford University Press, 1968).
15
Patrick Riley,
The General Will Before Rousseau: The Transformation of the Divine into the Civic
.
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986).
16
Instead, scholars often look for ways to subvert or disprove Jean-Jacques’ claim of consistency. The
most compelling example of this approach is Judith Shklar’s
Men and Citizens
. Shklar argued
forcefully that Rousseau was a deeply pessimistic thinker whose vision of secular redemption—of
cultivating men
and
citizens—was, by his own admission and example, fatally flawed. With due
respect, I believe that Shklar subverts his significant and sincere optimism (a value tied to his
religiosity) by exaggerating the extent and implications of his pessimism. Yet Rousseau’s writings did
not fall into the category of philosophical speculation he so loathed; he meant his vision to be
implemented in practice. We should, however, note that not all authors follow Shklar’s skeptical lead.
As much as anyone, Jean Starobinski struggled to identify the underlying coherence of Rousseau’s
work. In
La transparence et l’obstacle
, he noted the simultaneous piety and profanity that
characterized the Genevan’s morality, without taking this as evidence of his inconsistency. This work
is therefore in part an attempt to flesh out Starobinski’s claim, to determine where exactly Rousseau’s
opposed values coalesced within his singular vision of democratic virtue. See: Judith N. Shklar,
Men
7
made to use his concept of religion
against
him: to argue that his spiritual optimism is
fundamentally incoherent and incompatible with his political vision; that his Civil
Religion reveals a despotic, totalitarian temperament; and that his conversions from
Protestantism to Catholicism back to Protestantism attest to his capricious nature.
17
A fresh perspective is needed, one which defends Rousseau from these claims
by clarifying the significance of his religiosity, particularly as it informs a coherent
model of democratic virtue. Towards this end, we will explore the Pagan and
Christian traditions evident in concepts central to his life and writings; examine his
more contentious theological beliefs, particularly his sorely overlooked Pelagianism,
his proclamations of Christian faith, and his self-defense against the charges of heresy
brought against
Emile
; and explore how his simultaneous piety and profanity shapes a
compelling vision of political reform.
Drawing upon previous efforts, considerable space will be devoted to textual,
historical, and biographical analysis. We will also take seriously the abundant
misgivings put forth by Rousseau’s critics, and broach the question of his consistency
and coherence from the outset. In addition to addressing oft-overlooked figures (both
Pagan and Christian alike) crucial to fleshing out the complexity of his faith, we will
also explore Rousseau’s more neglected writings: the many letters, fragments, and
and Citizens: A Study of Rousseau’s Social Thought
. (London and New York: Cambridge University
Press, 1969); Jean Starobinski,
Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Transparency and Obstruction
. Arthur
Goldhammer, tr. (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1988). Originally published as
Jean-
Jacques Rousseau: La transparence et l’obstacle suivi de Sept essais sur Rousseau
. (Paris: Éditions
Gallimard, 1971).
17
See: J. L. Talmon,
The Origins of Totalitarian Democracy
. (London: Martin Secker & Warburg,
Ltd., 1952); Lester G. Crocker,
Rousseau’s Social Contract
. (Cleveland: Press of Case Western
Reserve University, 1968); Isaiah Berlin,
Four Essays on Liberty
. (New York: Oxford University
Press, 1969); J. H. Huizinga,
Rousseau: The Self Made Saint
. (New York: Viking Press, 1976); Arthur
M. Melzer,
The Natural Goodness of Man: On the System of Rousseau’s Thought
. (Chicago: The
University of Chicago Press, 1990).
8
minor works that supplement his (in)famous chapters
On Civil Religion
and the
Profession of Faith of a Savoyard Vicar
. Finally, we will examine Civil Religion as
the practical realization of Rousseau’s religious and secular convictions, before
concluding on the very path where he claimed his career began: the road to
Vincennes, where a life-changing revelation pressed him to serve both God and man.
Although we begin by introducing politico-theological relations as a tension
still-relevant (perhaps more than ever) to democratic theory, this is not a work of
public policy. It makes no claim to provide programmatic solutions to the
contentious relationship between religion and politics, nor even explicitly apply
Rousseau’s writings to contemporary problems. Nor, for that matter, is it an attempt
to draw linear relations between the Genevan and his Christian and Pagan forebears.
It rather suggests that Rousseau offers valuable insight into the relationship between
religion and politics; that his secular thought cannot be understood without reference
to his views on religion; and that his connection to such disparate figures as
Augustine and Pelagius, Diogenes and Saint Antony, Hobbes and Saint Paul, clarifies
the roots, innovations, and implications of Rousseau’s peculiar
18
faith. By examining
these inchoate influences, we may determine why Rousseau lauded religion yet was
so critical of religious dogmatism; why he was condemned as a heretic, despite
insisting upon his piety; and how his radical faith in man and God alike informed a
distinctly political vision of virtue with decidedly religious undertones. In the end, by
reconciling Rousseau’s uncompromising amalgam of spiritual and secular traditions,
18
According to
The Compact Edition of the Oxford English Dictionary
. (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1971), the term
peculiar
has two senses equally applicable to Rousseau’s faith: particular to him,
and highly unusual.
9
we will be poised not only to explain the necessity of religion to his thought, but also
glean a coherent political lesson from its role in the path to civic virtue.
10
Chapter 1: Strained Relations
On February 11, 1906, Pope Pius X unleashed an eloquent fury on the French
government. The object of his wrath was
La Loi concernant la séparation des
Églises et de l'État
(December 9, 1905), which instituted a formal separation between
church and state in France. In an elaborate Encyclical entitled
Vehementer Nos
, Pius
condemned the legislation on moral, political, practical and legal grounds, levying the
following censure on behalf of the Vatican:
We do, by virtue of the supreme authority which God has confided to
Us … reprove and condemn the law voted in France for the separation
of Church and State, as deeply unjust to God whom it denies, and as
laying down the principle that the Republic recognizes no cult. We
reprove and condemn it as violating the natural law, the law of nations,
and fidelity to treaties; as contrary to the Divine constitution of the
Church, to her essential rights and to her liberty; as destroying justice
and trampling underfoot the rights of property which the Church has
acquired by many titles and, in addition, by virtue of the Concordat.
We reprove and condemn it as gravely offensive to the dignity of the
Apostolic See, to Our own person, to the Episcopacy, and to the clergy
and all the Catholics of France. Therefore, We protest solemnly and
with all Our strength against the introduction, the voting and the
promulgation of this law, declaring that it can never be alleged against
the imprescriptible rights of the Church.” (§13)
19
Amongst his many specific charges, he concluded that French legislators were “guilty
of a great injustice to God” (§3). Evoking Augustine’s
City of God
, he argued that
the separation sabotaged the state’s “ultimate object which is man’s eternal happiness
after this short life shall have run its course.” (§3) Such disregard “inflicts great
injury on society itself, for it cannot either prosper or last long when due place is not
19
All section numbers refer to:
Vehementer Nos
, Encyclical of Pope Pius X, promulgated on February
11, 1906. All quotes are taken from the official Vatican translation.
11
left for religion, which is the supreme rule and the sovereign mistress in all questions
touching the rights and the duties of men.” (§3) The ruling betrayed a nation’s
ungratefulness, as France had been “during the course of centuries the object of…
great and special predilection on the part of the [Roman Catholic Church].” (§4) It
constituted a breach of international treaty law by unceremoniously revoking the
bilateral Concordat between the Roman Pontiff and the French Government. (§5)
La
Loi
also subverted a Papal hierarchy rooted in both divine and natural law, placing
“the Church under the domination of the civil power” (§7), and assigning “the
administration and the supervision of public worship… to an association formed of
laymen,” provisions which “seriously violate the rights of the Church, and are in
opposition with her Divine constitution.” (§8)
Labeling the legislation “an event of the gravest import, and one that must be
deplored by all the right-minded, for it is as disastrous to society as it is to religion,”
Pius admitted that “it is an event which surprised nobody who has paid any attention
to the religious policy followed in France of late years.” (§1) Indeed, though
La Loi
stands as the legal foundation of France’s separation between church and state, its
inception marked the culmination of a hundred-year movement towards strict
secularism. A process which began in 1792 during the short-lived First Republic, the
subsequent century saw a series of legislation which instituted a civil code (1804) and
civil marriage mandates (1810), abolished an 1814 law prohibiting work on Sundays
and holidays (1880), and barred public prayers before parliamentary sessions (1884).
During this period, France also secularized its schools and hospitals, enlisted clerics
in military service, banished Catholic practices and emblems from all public
12
establishments, and removed religious references from its judicial oath. The 1905
law formally upheld the spirit of these measures, reasserting on no uncertain terms
what had been a central theme of post-Jacobin politics: “La République assure la
liberté de conscience.”
20
The official separation of church and state, codified at the
start of the twentieth century, was deemed essential to protecting this liberty. By
prohibiting federal support of religious institutions, the ruling broadly denounced
preferential treatment towards any one particular faith;
égalité
, as much as
liberté
,
was the law’s guiding spirit.
It was not without concern, then, that a debate of some consequence began in
France in the early days of 2003. On January 17, according to
Le Monde
, Secretary
of State Pierre Bédier and government spokesman Jean-François Copé announced
unequivocally that
la Loi de 1905
was sorely in need of reform.
21
The catalysts to
this claim were the September 11, 2001 destruction of the World Trade Center,
subsequent bombings conducted by the Al Qaeda network, and a correlative fear of
future fundamentalist violence. As justification for his proposal, Bédier drew an
explicit connection between the dangers posed by Islamic extremism today and
Catholicism one hundred years prior: “In 1905, the government thought that Catholics
were anti-republican, and constituted a menace as such. Today, Islam poses a similar
problem. It would be unrealistic to ignore this concern.”
22
At heart of this debate are anxieties associated with the foreign financing of
Muslim mosques. Although
la Loi
explicitly prohibits public sponsorship of houses
20
La Loi concernant la séparation des Eglises et de l'Etat
, Article 1. Promulgated on July 3, 1905
with 314 votes for, 233 against.
21
“Faut-il réviser la loi de séparation des Eglises et de l’Etat?”
Le Monde
, January 17, 2003.
22
Ibid.,
Le Monde
, January 17, 2003.
13
of worship (a practice sometimes circumvented by partitions which establish ‘non-
prayer’ areas), there is growing concern that mosques are financed by persons or
organizations with terrorist ties or sympathies; that they might either serve as covert
terrorist communities, or distribute laundered funds to extremist cells within France;
and that state subsidization could effectively limit the amount of suspicious capital
entering from abroad. Alluding to both an “Islamic league” and unspecified Saudi
sources as possible perpetrators, Bédier cited the need for “extreme vigilance” in
regulating money arriving from ill-intentioned “foreign powers.”
23
An “Islam
of
France,” he argued, must supplant “Islam
in
France”—the religion must be sponsored
and regulated by the government, and not merely allowed to infiltrate the nation’s
borders.
24
Leaving aside the logic of this argument and the vagueness of its targets, the
proposal is radical: the state must oversee the affairs of one specific creed.
25
To
monitor mosques and prevent the laundering of “terrorist” funds, France must first
reform a hard-fought hallmark of its democracy (the strict separation of church and
state). To protect republican virtues, Bédier and Copé argue, they must revise a
paradigmatic republican law. Whereas in 1905 similar fears of Catholicism inspired a
strict separation of church and state, misgivings about Muslimism are now prompting
the French government to reconsider its abstention.
23
“Bédier souhaite un ‘islam de France’ et non plus un ‘islam en France.’”
Agence France-Presse
,
January 23, 2003.
24
If Bédier’s distinction is not terribly clear, we might consider it in relation to Rousseau, who was a
man
in
Paris but never considered himself a man
of
Paris. Ibid. (My emphasis.)
25
It is worth noting that this charge takes issue with the church (or, more precisely, the Mosque), and
not the religious practice itself.
14
The seeds for such revisionism had already been planted five years prior,
when, on October 7, 1998, the National Assembly unanimously approved
Décret n°
98-890
. The decree instituted
mission interministérielle de lutte contre les sects
(MILS), an interdepartmental effort which “incites public services to take, in respect
of public liberties, appropriate measures to anticipate and combat sects who
undermine personal human dignity or who threaten the public order.”
26
Under the
auspices of civic welfare—to “inform the public of the dangers posed by the sectarian
phenomenon”—the French government established an agency to officially monitor
religious factions.
27
These are striking examples of a democratic nation rethinking the interstices
of religion and politics, but not isolated ones. On December 12, 2002, George W.
Bush passed a unilateral Executive Order entitled “Equal Protection of the Laws for
Faith-based and Community Organizations.” This so-called “Faith-based initiative”
entitled religious groups to receive federal tax dollars for “social service programs”—
those which provide “services directed at reducing poverty, improving opportunities
for low-income children, revitalizing low-income communities, empowering low-
income families and low-income individuals to become self-sufficient, or otherwise
26
“Décret n° 98-890 du 7 octobre 1998 instituant une
mission interministérielle de lutte contre les
sectes
.” Taken from: Journal Officiel N° 234, du 9 Octobre 1998, page 15286.
27
Earlier in the same year, the United States passed the International Religious Freedom Act of 1998
“To express United States foreign policy with respect to, and to strengthen United States advocacy on
behalf of, individuals persecuted in foreign countries on account of religion.” According to the
subsequent “International Religious Freedom Report of 2002” released by the Bureau of Democracy,
Human Rights, and Labor, religious groups in France “continued to be concerned about the possible
impact of [recent] legislation passed,” although “no overall change in the status of respect for religious
freedom” was noted. See: “International Religious Freedom Act of 1998” (H.R. 2431), and the U.S.
Department of State “International Religious Freedom Report 2002: France.”
15
helping people in need.”
28
Immediately condemned by
The New York Times
as being
“unconstitutional, and fundamentally unfair,” and running “counter to decades of
First Amendment law, which holds that government dollars cannot be used to
promote religion,” the initiative has nonetheless garnered support from citizens of all
faiths who cite the growing need for spiritual guidance amongst charitable
organizations.
29
If the separation of church and state offers an essential foundation of a strong,
pluralist democracy, then the new millennium has begun on an ominous note. In very
different manners and for very different reasons, two of the world’s leading
democratic powers are redrawing the boundaries between secular and spiritual
institutions. In part, such revisionism is a sign of the times. Since September 11,
2001, ours has been a climate in which the ambiguous and ubiquitous use of the word
“terrorist” has supplanted “communist” as this era’s primary antonym for democracy,
and where terrorism is often conflated with Muslim fundamentalism. Yet amidst this
atmosphere of mistrust, western nations have increasingly embraced another creed—
Christianity—for guidance in social, moral, political, and educational reform.
30
If
France has deemed Islam a potential threat to republican order and “public liberties,”
the United States has approached faith-based groups as heretofore neglected sources
28
George W. Bush, “Equal Protection of the Laws for Faith-based and Community Organizations.”
Executive Order 13279 of December 12, 2002.
29
“Using Tax Dollars for Churches.”
The New York Times
, December 30, 2002.
30
Shortly after the World Trade Center attacks, British Prime Minister Tony Blair proposed increasing
state-funding for religious schools as part of a New Labour Party plan to reform secondary education.
Although roughly 7,000 of Britain’s 25,000 schools already have religious affiliations, the measure
was in part seen as a means of luring middle class families—an increasing number of whom send
children to privately financed schools—back to the public sector. More recently (in 2002), Polish
president Aleksander Kwasniewski successfully solicited Pope John Paul II to raise public support for
inclsion into the European Union, arguing that such an alliance would help to “restore Christian
values in Western Europe.” See: “Tony and the little children” (
The Economist
, December 6, 2001);
“Preaching for the European Union” (
The Economist
, March 14, 2002).
16
of “helping people in need.” Whether guided by skeptical mistrust or philanthropic
idealism, such divergent positions and policies reveal a common conviction:
democracies cannot ignore the civic significance (for better or worse) of religious
associations. Furthermore, in both instances (and no matter the motives) the end
result is similar: democratic states are increasingly involved in religious affairs.
Given these turns of events, we may well ask: was Nietzsche wrong? When
the prophetic German foretold the death of God, when he heralded that “belief in the
Christian god has become unbelievable,” had he spoken too soon?
31
Ours is certainly
an age of scientific rationalism and global capitalism, of a liberalism whose most
visible ambassadors travel through television and film, music and internet lines. Pat
Buchanan’s infamous “Culture War” speech and his Republican National Convention
address of 1992 were both offensive and vitriolic, but were they
entirely
far-
fetched?
32
America
does
seem awash in the godless libertinism of popular culture;
the nuclear family
is
a dying unit; we
are
increasingly tolerant, and
do
parade our
sexual, ethnic and political diversity with pride rather than shame.
But ours is equally an age of religious resurgence, of Jihad and missionaries,
of the sudden
integration
of church and state. According to
The Economist
,
Millenarianism—the fundamentalist “belief in the thousand-year reign of King
Jesus”—has appealed to broader audiences since September 11, a rise evidenced by
both its popularity amongst conservative radio station audiences, and the soaring sales
31
Friedrich Nietzsche,
The Gay Science
, Walter Kaufmann, tr. (New York: Random House, Inc.,
1974), §343, p. 279.
32
According to Buchanan, “There is a religious war going on in our country for the soul of America. It
is a cultural war, as critical to the kind of nation we will one day be as was the Cold War itself.” See:
Patrick J. Buchanan, “1992 Republican National Convention Speech” (August 17, 1992). Similarly, in
his speech entitled “The Cultural War for the Soul of America” (September 14, 1992), Buchanan asks:
“Are we any longer ‘one nation under God,’ or has one-half of that nation already begun to secede
from the other?”
17
of the bestselling evangelical novel series “Left Behind” which molds a message of
Old Testament fire-and-brimstone fury to isolationist politics.
33
Even more centrally,
membership in Christian churches exceeded two billion in the new millennium, a
growth of roughly 1.2 billion over 30 years.
34
In America alone, the number of
Christians have risen by over 200 percent in the past 50 years (to 171 million);
membership in churches of all faiths now comprises over 60 percent of the
population, or roughly twice what it was in the mid-nineteenth century. These
circumstances should give us pause. Has the “cheerfulness” Nietzsche saw in a
Europe released from the shadow of God already begun to fade, in both the Continent
and the New World?
Clearly, Nietzsche’s assertion is debatable now, just as it was when written.
In 1885, three years following the publication of the first edition of
The Gay
Science
,
35
Pope Leo XIII described church-state relations in organic terms, arguing
that “[t]here must … exist between these two powers a certain orderly connection,
which may be compared to the union of the soul and body in man.”
36
What the
German reviled as a slavish specter haunting human livelihood, the Roman extolled
as natural and necessary. What Nietzsche attacked as systematic self-inurement, Leo
XIII lauded as both physically and spiritually healthy. Neither vision triumphed
wholly. The relationship between religious and political institutions is
still
hotly
33
The first book alone (of this as yet nine-book series) has sold over 7 million copies to date. See:
Lexington, “Behold the Rapture.”
The Economist
, August 22, 2002.
34
“The fight for God.”
The Economist
, December 19, 2002.
35
Nietzsche first writes of “the death of God” in
The Gay Science
, §108. He also discusses this
phenomenon in §343, as well as in
Thus Spoke Zarathustra
pp. 124f., 191, 202, 294, 371-379, 398f. in
The Portable Nietzsche
, Walter Kaufmann, tr. (New York: The Viking Press, 1954).
36
Immortale Dei
, Encyclical of Pope Leo XIII, promulgated on November 1, 1885.
18
contested, particularly when drawing boundaries according to liberal democratic
principles of neutrality and equality under law.
A tension clearly relevant to contemporary democratic discourse, less evident
is how it may be resolved. Perhaps religion generally is neither reducible to the
philanthropic salvation central to Bush’s vision, nor the vengeful violence of
fundamentalist terrorism. Perhaps its relationship to democracy is significantly more
complicated, and begs further examination, rather than the reactionary regulation and
surveillance advocated by Bédier and Copé. To arrive at a more nuanced assessment
we might turn to a thinker whose beliefs encompassed both poles, one enamored with
and
mistrustful of religion’s relationship to the secular state, who identified spiritual
faith as a cornerstone of civic morality, and spiritual associations as potentially
divisive sources of intolerance and exclusion. To better assess the relationship
between religion and politics generally, and Christianity and democracy specifically,
we might cast our gaze back to one of the first modern democrats, himself a
Protestant:
37
Jean-Jacques Rousseau.
* * * * *
It is within Rousseau that we find both piousness and profanity, a secular
theodicy in which man (rather than God) bears the burdens of enacting his own
salvation. Standing at a pivotal crossroads in political thought, one where
37
Although Rousseau was born a Protestant, he converted to Catholicism at the age of 16. For
Rousseau’s own account, see:
The Confessions
, CW V.38-40; OC I.45-47. In
The Reveries of the
Solitary Walker
(Third Promenade), Rousseau adds this: “Given into my own keeping while still a
child and enticed by caresses, seduced by vanity, lured by hope, forced by necessity, I became a
Catholic, but I always remained a Christian.” CW IX.19; OC I.1013. For Rousseau’s description of
his rejoining the Protestant faith in 1754, see: CW V.329-330; OC I.392-393.
19
Enlightenment
philosophes
challenged the theologism dominant since the age of
Augustine, the Genevan straddled awkward lines indeed. On one hand he was a
compelling secularist, a prolific author who championed radical reform drawn
according to democratic principles of liberty and equality. Rousseau’s vision of
legitimate sovereignty was rooted in the common will of citizens (rather than God),
and supported by the primacy of positive law. Yet he was also enraptured with an
incomprehensibly harmonious divine order revealed in nature, and urged men to
willfully follow their God-given conscience to live in greater accord with this
heavenly example.
Incorporating both Christian and secular sources within a singular model of
legitimate democratic governance, Rousseau illustrates one possible means of
reconciling religion and politics. Guided by a dual sense of past failings and future
potential,
38
he neither categorically dismissed nor blindly accepted the compatibility
of corporeal and spiritual associations. Indeed, despite arguing for their integration,
Rousseau took seriously the premise that man’s earthly and otherworldly needs can
be either mutually exclusive
or
mutually enriching; the choice, as he presents it, is
entirely up to us. Religion can serve as a shared source of moral duty, a means of
unifying individuals and cultivating our natural sense of brotherly love. It can also
breed artificial divisions between people of different creeds, acting as a catalyst to the
sectarianism and violent persecution so destructive of common welfare. Religion can
38
Elsewhere I describe this dual sense of past failings and future potential as
pessimistic realism
and
heuristic idealism
. These two stances are two mutually constitutive within Rousseau’s work. His deep
dissatisfaction with the status quo pressed to him envision a better possible future, even as it forced
him to recognize the difficulties in bringing about substantive change. This phenomenon is
particularly evident in his assessment of positive religion: Rousseau’s condemnation of Catholicism
provided impetus for him to found a more virtuous, civil alternative.
20
damn man to hell, and also nurture a sense of interdependence and faith in better
times. As with politics, it can adopt different
forms
, some legitimate, some coercive;
some enriching, some self-destructive; some polarizing, some unifying. If papist
dogma presented an example of religion at its most harmful, Rousseau struggled to
clarify the terms of a truly beneficial piety: one that cultivated reverence towards God
and
man, binding us to our fellows, community and Creator alike.
The faith upon which his vision rested was paradoxical in both senses of the
word: it contradicted the commonly held truths of his age, and drew upon apparently
incompatible beliefs in man’s intrinsic innocence and his capacity for wickedness.
Directly refuting orthodox Roman Catholicism, Rousseau revived the Pelagian heresy
that humankind was naturally good. Yet this belief was qualified by his equally
vociferous insistence upon man’s capacity for wickedness, a propensity evidenced by
our well-documented history of decline. His solution to the problem of theodicy
39
—
namely, the question of how evil can exist in a world created by an omnipotent
God—forced us to consider salvation in secular terms, taking recourse in the very
faculties and traits (willing, pride, perfectionism) that led us astray from our
inherently pure natures. Yet he never failed to remind men of their self-incurred
failings, the degree to which they had strayed from their state of natural harmony.
Rousseau’s theory of redemption was simultaneously informed by this pessimistic
view of human history and optimistic assessment of human nature; if man had made a
mess of society, he also possessed the capacity to correct his self-incurred failings.
Unlike Augustine, for whom free will offered a moral test geared towards post-
39
To compare Rousseau’s views with those of Leibniz see:
Theodicy
I.7-8. For Rousseau’s self-
distancing from Leibniz see:
Letter to Philopolis
. CW III.129-130; OC III.232-234.
21
mortem salvation (and thus comprised God’s gift to humankind), man replaced God
as the facilitator of a salvation possible in
this
world and
this
lifetime.
However, far from absolving religion of a role in politics Rousseau
appropriated Christian tropes to serve civic ends, through secular measures. His
portrait of human history evoked a fall of Biblical proportions, yet he framed the
means of possible redemption in exclusively corporeal terms.
40
In this, the Genevan’s
formula stood in sharp contrast to his Christian voluntarist forebears. Augustine
understood divine forgiveness as the sole antidote to Adam’s debilitating legacy.
Salvation, if at all possible, lay in God’s merciful grace; human lives were grueling
trials of which conformity was the aim. Life was best served by emulating, to the
best of our meager human ability, a magnificent, unified divine will. Luther and
Calvin shared this sentiment, arguing that man had little recourse to alter his divinely-
determined fate.
41
For Luther, the “false idea of ‘free-will’ is a real threat to
salvation, and a delusion fraught with the most perilous consequences”—namely, the
misguided premise that human agency influences divine redemption.
42
Calvin
likewise insisted that the human will was emphatically not free, meaning neither
40
It can be argued that this is untrue of all of Rousseau’s works. To wit,
Julie
and the
Reveries
seek
solace to varying degrees (and for varying reasons) after life ends. But even these aims are established
after
earthly remedies have apparently failed. Transcendent post-mortem redemption is a last resort,
rather than (as for Augustine) a guiding principle. Although this tension will be examined in greater
detail in later chapters, I will side here with Starobinski, who urges his readers to locate consistency in
Jean-Jacques’ work. Clearly, the bulk of the Genevan’s writings grapple with secular solutions to
moral and political problems.
41
There are obviously crucial differences between Luther and Calvin, not least of which involves the
latter’s emphasis upon the role of good works in gauging the possibility of election. For the purposes
of this introduction, however, they both fall under the broad rubric of Protestant voluntarism, under
whose terms God alone affects salvation.
42
Martin Luther, “Bondage of the Will,” in
Martin Luther: Selections from His Writings
, John
Dillenberger, tr. and ed. (New York: Anchor Books, 1961), p. 189.
22
strictly autonomous nor capable of emulating a divine, omnipotent will.
43
Salvation
rested solely on the shoulders of God, whose will alone dictated an individual’s fate.
In breaking with this tradition, Rousseau understood our decline as a temporal
crisis in need of earthly solutions. The woeful state of human affairs—emblematized
by the ironic “triumph” of science and reasoning over nature—was empirically
demonstrable throughout history, evidenced by growing inequality and individual
alienation from our harmonious, divine natures. Rousseau’s ambivalent view of
progress did not, however, cause him to categorically condemn humankind as
inherently sinful. Rather, modern society was the object of his scorn, a source of
moral indeterminacy in need of a political balm. Two thousand years prior, Socrates
famously argued that men never knowingly commit evil: acts of ill-repute revealed
ignorance more than malfeasance.
44
As Ernst Cassirer rightly noted, eighteenth
century thinkers clarified this sentiment, condemning “not ignorance as such, but
ignorance which pretends to be truth and wants to pass for truth.”
45
Self-delusion—
that which “inflicts the mortal wound on knowledge”—found its most egregious form
in superstition. Presaging Kant, who famously described enlightenment as “
man’s
43
See: John Calvin,
On God and Political Duty, Second Revised Edition
, John Allen and Benjamin B.
Warfield, eds. (New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc., 1956);
Institutes of the Christian
Religion in Two Volumes
, John T. McNeill, ed. and Ford Lewis Battles, tr. (Philadelphia: The
Westminster Press, 1960).
44
As Socrates argued in
Timaeus
(86d), “almost all those affections which are called by way of
reproach ‘incontinence in pleasure,’ as though the wicked acted voluntarily, are wrongly so
reproached; for no one is voluntarily wicked.” Similarly, he asserted in
Protagoras
(345d-345e) that
“I am fairly certain that no wise man believes anyone sins willingly or willingly perpetrates any evil or
base act. They know very well that all evil or base action is involuntary.” And finally, the Athenian
argued in
The Laws
(731c-731d) that “no unjust man is ever voluntarily unjust. For no one anywhere
would ever voluntarily take the greatest evil into his most honorable possession and keep it for the rest
of his life. So the unjust man, like the man who possesses bad things, is pitiable in every way, and it is
permissible to pity such a man when his illness is curable.” See:
Protagoras and Meno
, W.K.C.
Guthrie, tr. (New York: Penguin Books, 1956), pp. 80-81;
The Laws of Plato
, Thomas L. Pangle, tr.
(Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1988), p. 117.
45
Ernst Cassirer,
The Philosophy of the Enlightenment
, Fritz C. A. Koelln & James P. Pettegrove, trs.
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1951), p. 161.
23
emergence from his self-incurred immaturity
… [namely] the inability to use one’s
own understanding without the guidance of another,”
46
Rousseau expounded upon
this idea, arguing that doing good depends on knowing and actively pursuing the
good, a goal realized through education, and fortification against the vain temptations
cultivated by societal pressures. Such practical wisdom was gleaned through sober
assessment and individual effort, rather than revelation or divine intervention.
47
Hobbes had also stayed the hand of God in arguing for a radical corporeal
solution to the pressing problems of political instability and resultant (apolitical)
anarchy.
48
Yet whereas Jean-Jacques’
Social Contract
promised virtuous rapture, the
Englishman’s renunciation of individual will (to the Monarch’s authority) offered a
more physical assurance: protection in a world torn asunder by the war of all against
all. Hobbesian psychology, rooted in a hedonistic physics of appetite and aversion,
allowed little room for nuance much less transcendence. His was a world-view in
which crisis was a universal condition; humankind had little hope for stability beyond
self-abrogating, strong-armed rule. As Charles Taylor noted, Hobbes “thought of our
world picture as almost literally put together out of building blocks—which were
ultimately the sensations or ideas produced by experience.”
49
By contrast,
Rousseau’s puzzle was built of more awkward pieces: innocence and guilt,
46
Immanuel Kant, “An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?” in
Political Writings
,
Second Enlarged Edition
, Hans Reiss, ed. and H.B. Nisbet, tr. (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1991), p. 54.
47
As we will discuss, Rousseau also stressed the necessity of following our divinely-instilled
conscience, although he recognized the acute difficulties this task posed to denatured, socialized
creatures.
48
This statement follows the basic assumption of C.B. MacPherson, who saw in Hobbes’ “state of
nature” a thinly-veiled description of Civil War-torn England. See:
The Political Theory of Possessive
Individualism: Hobbes to Locke
. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1962), pp. 64-67.
49
Charles Taylor,
Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity
. (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1989), p. 197.
24
involvement and retreat, freedom and chains, individual liberty facilitated by
conformity to divine order and corporeal sovereignty, historical decline and the
possibility of secular salvation.
50
Given Rousseau’s cacophonous terms, and the critical tone of his own
exegeses, a specific problem confronts us from the outset: how can man claim purity
of heart if history (and Jean-Jacques himself) suggest quite the opposite? It is
tempting to suppose that he cannot: the evidence weighs too heavily against him.
Following Rousseau’s own account, society is of man’s making;
amour propre
and
urbanity are perverse
human
predilections. Given this assessment, Jean-Jacques’
insistence upon individual innocence seems inconsistent at best. Redemption, after
all, presupposes guilt. One cannot rise again without having first fallen. In the
Christian tradition, the source of our guilt (free will) is axiomatic; in Rousseau’s
analysis, blame is more ambiguous. Although Jean-Jacques follows a Biblical
narrative replete with innocence, corruption, and redemption, he insists throughout
that individuals
en générale
are not culpable because we are not beholden to Adam’s
sinful legacy.
51
He adheres to an orthodox narrative of decline, while subverting the
very foundations of Roman Catholic ontology. Yet perhaps this tension is not as
incoherent as it might appear. Recalling Rousseau’s famous plea to forgive him of
his paradoxes,
52
the dialectic born of these competing visions serves a substantive
purpose: it makes Rousseau’s visionary perfectionism remarkably compelling. The
50
As we will discuss, Rousseau also maintained his faith in eternal redemption. Indeed, following his
exile after the publication of
Emile
, he increasingly embraced the afterlife as a source of solace, a point
when God (in contrast to his peers) would recognize and reward his goodness.
51
As we will examine in Chapters 2 and 3, this proved to be Rousseau’s most controversial paradox.
52
“Common readers, pardon me my paradoxes. They are necessary when one reflects, and no matter
what you might say, I prefer to be a man of paradoxes than a man of prejudices.” OC IV.323; E 93.
25
strength of his solution lies in its stubbornness, in its steadfast adherence to both
Biblical form
and
secular means. It is powerful precisely because it speaks of
salvation, and identifies common man as catalytic agent.
Writing amidst an age of accelerated spiritual debauchery, of urbanization and
cosmopolitan hubris, Rousseau finds redemption in the very faculties which have led
humankind to stray from its sympathetic nature. We can, the abbreviated lesson goes,
save ourselves only by being true to ourselves: by redirecting our naturally pure wills,
and recasting the objects of our desires. A shepherd of sorts, Jean-Jacques challenges
us to follow him in simply
being
, in cultivating our intrinsically virtuous natures on a
moral and practical path towards earthly redemption. Although we are good at heart,
society has swayed our judgment and clouded our conscience. We must therefore re-
educate ourselves, solidify our resolution with Spartan fortitude and forge a strong
general will to combat the errant appetites of modern particularism. More precisely,
the means of existential improvement employ the very faculties (such as self-interest)
which have perverted our natural goodness. Man himself has strayed from a virtuous
course, and man himself must right his own ship. Prophetic punch combined with
clear heresy: such is Rousseau’s attachment to and break from orthodox theological
discourse, a dissonant rupture that begs clarification.
Examining the confluence of theological and secular sources in Rousseau’s
work therefore serves three purposes. First, it reveals which aspects of his philosophy
are Pagan in origin and which are indebted to earlier Christian traditions. Second, it
clarifies both the radical, paradoxical newness of Rousseau’s vision (how it departed
from existent tradition and commonly held opinion) and the genuine connectedness
26
he shared with Christian voluntarism.
53
And third, exploring these linkages offers a
means of reassessing the relationship between spiritual and secular values. Using
Rousseau as a lens, we might revisit a “strong” model of democracy enriched and
invigorated by its diverse roots, one that sacrifices neither earthly nor otherworldly
welfare, balances a skeptical view of positive religion with an undying faith in divine
order, and encourages us to move beyond the overly simplistic dichotomies that
characterize discussions of the relationship between religion and politics.
Given these terms, this work is best understood as descriptive, restorative and
argumentative. Descriptive, in that it identifies Rousseau’s appropriation of both
Christian and Pagan concepts of virtue. Restorative, in that it involves—not unlike
either
Confessions
—the recollection and attempted reconciliation of these divided
(conceptual) histories. And argumentative, in that it finds within Rousseau’s
awkward alliance of conflicting traditions a compelling means of incorporating
religion into the fabric of a virtuous democracy.
In
l’Ancien régime et la révolution
, Alexis de Tocqueville argued that the
Jacobin “campaign against all forms of religion was merely incidental to the French
Revolution, a spectacular but transient phenomenon, a brief reaction to the ideologies,
emotions, and events which led up to it—but in no sense basic to its program.”
54
This
work is also, therefore, in part a rejoinder to the prescient Frenchman. I use
53
We may consequently read Rousseau not simply as a “modern” with “ancient” affinities, but as a
complicated amalgam of competing philosophical, political, ontological and religious world-views.
Allan Bloom famously disagreed. As he argued, the “Quarrel between the Ancients and the Moderns”
dominated philosophical discourse in the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries. For Bloom, “[n]o
issue is more important in the history of thought, and Rousseau emphatically takes the side of the
ancients… at least so far as literature and morals are concerned.” Although this conclusion is lacking
in nuance, we might still accept his claim that “[n]o study of Rousseau can be serious which does not
take seriously ‘The Quarrel.’” See: Bloom,
Emile
, p. 492 n. 86.
54
Alexis de Tocqueville,
The Old Regime and the French Revolution
, Stuart Gilbert, tr. (New York:
Anchor Books/Doubleday, 1955), pp. 5-6.
27
“rejoinder” rather than “repudiation” because I agree with Tocqueville’s basic
premise: the spirit of the French Revolution seemed rightly cosmopolitan, and
aggressively agonistic; it aimed at the overhaul of
humankind
, a revision which
heralded the death of obsolete hierarchies and mores, secular and spiritual institutions
alike. Yet
l’Ancien régime
errs in drawing a sharp distinction between supposedly
enlightened, anarchistic, revolutionary upheaval and the attack of specific political
and religious institutions.
55
As Rousseau’s writings make plain, the political landscape of pre-
revolutionary France was dominated by papal interests. Political reform
required
religious reform because the two authorities were so deeply linked. Although
Tocqueville concurred, in
Democracy and America
he also identified the New
World’s religiosity as a primary source of its admirably fierce liberal spirit.
56
According to Tocqueville, religion (free of clerical dogmatism) fostered community
and solidarity, a phenomenon exemplified by American constitutional faith. Given
this predilection, it should come as no surprise that when assessing his native land he
carefully distinguished between the populist “resuscitation” of man and the “studious
ferocity” of anti-Church sentiment.
57
He was quick to draw a line between popular
sovereignty and anti-religiosity because, as America demonstrated, the two were not
mutually dependent. Yet in so doing, Tocqueville concealed a point I will attempt to
problematize: that the democratic revolution envisioned by Rousseau was both
55
Readers should note that although Tocqueville argues that the events of 1789 were neither explicitly
political nor religious in aim, he nonetheless details similarities between the Reformation and the
French Revolution. Ibid., §I.3.
56
As with Rousseau, Tocqueville’s writings force a crucial distinction between anticlericalism and
irreligiosity. Arguing that papists exerted a corrupting influence upon the
ancient régime
, he also held
that America’s religious spirit was a crucial component of its robust civic culture.
57
Tocqueville,
The Old Regime and the French Revolution
, p. 6.
28
indebted to and radically dismissive of theological tradition. If Jean-Jacques praised
religiosity’s moral role within secular polities, so did he repudiate papal authority
(which cultivated subordination and political alienation) and Catholic ontology
(rooted in the narrative of Original Sin).
58
According to Rousseau, society could hardly rise from the ashes of our self-
incurred wickedness were we not first been able to place trust in our intrinsic
innocence
as creations of a benevolent deity. Nor, more generally, could the French
Revolution have occurred
sans le Siècle des lumières
, an age characterized by its
simultaneous embrace of reason and sharp critique of clericalism. Although Voltaire,
Diderot, Helvétius, Holbach and d’Alembert made Church-bashing a spectator sport,
far less obvious is the degree to which this period of thought—like, following
Tocqueville, the Jacobin fervor and the France of his day—was still deeply mired in
Christian tropes of redemption, rebirth and enlightenment itself.
59
Rousseau offers
the best example of a thinker at such a nexus of spiritual faith and scientific reason,
one whose work at turns drew upon and rejected both traditional theology
and
Enlightenment rationalism.
58
This is not to say that democracy and Christian ontology are necessarily mutually exclusive, but
rather to stress this relationship within Rousseau’s works.
59
By contrast, David P. Jordan argues the following: “Robespierre would speak at significant moments
in his career about some providential scheme of which he was a part, but his providence is so
politically conceived, so deliberately tailored to the immediate needs of the French Revolution, that it
would be wrong to think of these appeals in traditional religious terms.” Although the French
Revolution falls beyond the immediate scope of this work, I would argue merely in passing that this
assertion follows the “error” already identified in Tocqueville: that the semantic and substantive use of
“providence,” in this instance, does reveal a connection to “traditional religious terms,” even if these
terms are opportunistically, politically, purposefully, or even perversely employed. See Jordan,
The
Revolutionary Career of Maximilien Robespierre
. (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1985),
p. 9.
29
This dialectical quality permeated Rousseau’s religious, political and
biographical
60
works alike. As Pierre Hadot rightly notes, the Genevan consistently
conveyed “both the echo of ancient traditions and the anticipation of certain modern
attitudes.”
61
A radical visionary wedded to classical virtue, he applied a deeply
Protestant perfectionism to secular politics. No stranger to personal sin,
62
he waged a
veritable holy war of innocence regained in hell-bent times. From the early spitfire of
the discourses, to his final
Reveries
(whose longing spirit is well-captured by
Matthew 5:8: “Blessed are the pure of heart for they shall see God”), Rousseau’s was
a will at war not so much with itself—unlike Augustine—but with society. He drew
an emphatic line in the sand, daring men of letters to quell the revolution of the
common man
: he was the harbinger of a revolution in politics founded firmly upon
the broad shoulders of
les peuples
, their exemplar and liberator alike.
Given the severity of Rousseau’s project—his do-or-die terms, his moral
righteousness—it should come as no surprise that the standard range of critiques
applied to Jean-Jacques mirrors modern critiques of Christianity’s place in politics.
The Genevan was, by diverse accounts, anything from a hopeless Utopist to a proto-
60
Rousseau makes his life central to his political philosophy. He wrote numerous autobiographical
texts (
The Confessions
,
The Dialogues
, and the
Reveries
, as well as fragments, documents, and letters)
that, significantly, comprise the first volume of the Pléaide edition of his
Oeuvres Complètes
. The
bulk of his additional works also bear marks of intimacy: he addressed readers as Jean-Jacques,
revealed intimate details of his life, and stressed the openness of his writings as a testament of his
honesty and sincerity. As such, any study of Rousseau must recognize the unusual personal tenor of
his works, and treat his life as he suggested: as a text to be read in conjunction with his more
traditional philosophical and political writings. Towards this end, Christopher Kelly succeeds
wonderfully with
Rousseau’s Exemplary Life: The Confessions as Political Philosophy
.
61
Pierre Hadot,
Philosophy as a Way of Life
, Michael Chase, tr. and Arnold I. Davison, ed. (Oxford:
Blackwell Publishers Ltd., 1995), p. 259.
62
In
The Confessions
, Rousseau admits to—amongst other things—a bizarre sexual appetite (being
spanked, flashing strangers), his erotic relationship with the older Mme. de Warens (whom he called
‘maman’), his escapades with various women in France, the abandonment of his children on the
footsteps of an orphanage, and lying and thieving as a youth.
30
Totalitarian.
63
These charges prove equally worthy of consideration when applied to
Christianity, which classically urges men to place faith in an afterlife, to renounce
their individual desires and conform to a divine will. There is a reason such critiques
are levied against both Christianity and Rousseau—both tradition and man are prone
to similar excesses. Prominent authors from Tocqueville to, more recently, William
Galston and Manning Marable have argued for the inclusion of religious groups into
the fabric of pluralist politics.
64
But compelling evidence suggests that religion
in
practice
—the positive worship and tenets of organized congregations and creeds—is
the proverbial oil to democratic water, a force historically at odds with popular
sovereignty.
65
Democracy is, after all, a politics of pragmatic consensus reflective of its
citizenry’s general will. Rule of the masses can hardly be confused with Platonic
elevation or Christian humility. The strength of democratic theory rather lies in its
emphasis upon the common good, an embrace of temporal progress
and
potential. A
government which allows each to pursue his own vision without infringing upon the
rights of others surely upholds these values. Yet perhaps a democracy which also
adopts transcendent plateaus offers a productive balance to pure proceduralism.
Succumbing neither to the surreal remoteness ridiculed by Aristophanes,
66
nor the dry
63
See: J. L. Talmon,
The Origins of Totalitarian Democracy
; Lester G. Crocker,
Rousseau’s Social
Contract
; Isaiah Berlin,
Four Essays on Liberty
; J. H. Huizinga,
Rousseau: The Self Made Saint
;
Arthur M. Melzer,
The Natural Goodness of Man: On the System of Rousseau’s Thought
.
64
See: William A. Galston,
Liberal Pluralism: The Implications of Value Pluralism for Political
Theory and Practice
. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002); Manning Marable,
The Great
Wells of Democracy: The Meaning of Race in American Life
. (New York: BasicCivitas Books, 2002).
65
As we will discuss in Chapter 5, Rousseau himself makes precisely this point in
On Civil Religion
.
66
See:
The Clouds
in
Four Plays by Aristophanes
, William Arrowsmith, Richard Lattimore, and
Douglass Parker, trs. (New York: Meridian, 1994).
31
conciliation pioneered by Dewey,
67
we may foster a democracy guided by a vigorous
dialectic between reason and spirit, pragmatism and idealism, what
is
and what
ought
to be
.
68
Might we not, as Rousseau did, keep one foot firmly planted on our home
turf, whilst our gaze is cast towards a better future?
The problem, of course, is that a politics which seeks both the
here and now
and the proverbial
pie in the sky
seems divided by mutually exclusive aims. Karl
Lowith made precisely this point regarding modernity writ large, arguing that modern
man is tragically torn between competing senses of history.
69
“The modern mind,” he
wrote, “has not made up its mind whether it should be Christian or Pagan. It sees
with one eye of faith and one eye of reason.”
70
The modern world “is the outcome of
an age-long process of secularization”; it is “worldly and irreligious and yet
dependent on the Christian creed from which it is emancipated”; in sum, “it is
Christian by derivation and anti-Christian by consequence.”
71
Georges Poulet located a like-minded dissonance in contemporary concepts of
time.
72
During the Eighteenth Century, he observed, “[m]an is revealed as the
feckless creator of man,” an awkward burden under which we invariably fail to meet
our own lofty, self-imposed standards.
73
Echoing Nietzsche, he argued that amidst
this intoxicating moment “man suddenly feels for the first time in the Christian era
that the instant of his existence is an instant free of all dependence, liberated from all
67
See: John Dewey,
The Public and Its Problems
. (Athens, Ohio: Swallow Press/Ohio University
Press, 1954).
68
Again, readers should consult:
The Social Contract
. CW IV.131; OC III.351.
69
See Karl Lowith,
Meaning in History
, (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1949), especially
pp. 19, 194, 207.
70
Ibid., p. 207.
71
Ibid., pp. 201-202
72
See Georges Poulet,
Studies in Human Time
, Elliott Coleman, tr. (New York: The Johns Hopkins
Press, 1956), especially pp. 25-29.
73
Poulet, p. 26.
32
duration, equal to all its own potentialities … It knows itself to be faultless.”
74
Although neither Poulet nor Lowith specifically addressed Rousseau in these
instances, the Genevan is not above either charge. Caught between ancient and
modern notions of fraternity and autonomy, societal guilt and individual innocence,
future grace and corporeal redemption, perfectionism and fallibility, Jean-Jacque’s
“man” stood at a complicated crossroads indeed.
How, then, did people and politics look for Rousseau, in the real world? To
paraphrase Christopher Wallace,
was it all a dream
, or are his reveries coherent?
75
If
we follow Lowith and Poulet, perhaps not. Perhaps the confluence of modern and
ancient, Christian and secular, divine and human, subverts the constancy
characteristic of a strong theory. But perhaps we may yet accept these analyses and
still find in their effects some measure of strength: not one gleaned from the sole
standard of either Christian piety or Pagan virtue, but from a democratic amalgam
enriched by its eclectic roots. Was this not the conclusion Rousseau himself
solicited? Appropriating contrasting traditions within a single model of reform, he
forced us to envision a democratic polity supported by religious practice, one which
sacrificed neither the spiritual nor secular welfare of its citizens.
This was a peculiar reverie indeed. As Jean Starobinski rightly notes,
“Rousseau formule sans doute ici une morale toute profane, mais elle ne se comprend
qu’en référence à un modèle religieux.”
76
Jean-Jacques himself told us as much. He
slammed his ill-matched cards on the table for all to see, calling our bluff. He alone
was a virtuous
homme á Paris
, wandering much as Diogenes the Cynic combed
74
Poulet, p. 21.
75
Notorious B.I.G., “Juicy.” From the album:
Ready to Die
, Bad Boy Records, 1994.
76
Starobinski,
La transparence et l’obstacle
, p. 83 (tr. p. 63).
33
Athens’ streets nearly four centuries Before Christ, searching with lit lantern in broad
daylight for another real man.
77
With the original Cynic’s force, and religious zeal,
Jean-Jacques dared us to follow him in enacting a plan previously left in God’s hands.
The bait lies in full sight: Spartan stoicism and civil religion; a defense of natural
innocence corrupted by artifice and hubris; Enlightenment Deism which rejects
philosophe
atheism; a patriotic hymn shunned by Geneva; Rousseau’s own
conversion from Protestantism to Catholicism, back to Protestantism; an ode to fallen
man (both himself and others) raised by the sheer force of his own divinely-guided
will; the fervor of a vision which accepts no compromise. If Rousseau’s secular
stylings marginalized divinity as never before, they bore the divine marks of an all-
seeing eye and a master plan. It is, in the final analysis, this mixture of piousness and
profanity that makes the Genevan’s prescriptions so provocative.
By fleshing out this challenging dialectic, we might achieve some measure of
clarity regarding Rousseau’s peculiar faith generally, and his practical contribution to
the reconciliation of religion and politics specifically. Plagued by potentially
irreconcilable divisions, how does his amalgam of Christian and Pagan ideals allow
us to reconceptualize the relationship between spiritual and secular values within
democratic polities? Are Rousseau’s contradictory aims fatally debilitating? Does he
merely prop humankind up to fail, charging us with a task (secular salvation) we are
incapable of fulfilling? Or do his discordant sources offer an unlikely foundation for
democratic meliorism, specifically one that recognizes a positive role for religion?
77
Diogenes Laertius,
Lives of Eminent Philosophers: Volume II
, R.D. Hicks, tr. (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1925), p. 43.
34
It is my belief—and this work’s central argument—that Rousseau offers a
uniquely revealing lens through which to examine the tensions between religion and
politics. Yet because the value of his contribution lies precisely in its recourse to
conflicting traditions (Pagan and Christian) and sentiments (deep pessimism and
profound optimism), the coherence and (dare we say) utility of his paradoxical project
is far from self-evident. Attacked as heretical, Rousseau’s reverie of secular salvation
drew heavily upon Christian ideals and assumptions. Mistrustful of religious
associations, he urged us to accept divine reverence as a foundation for moral duty
and civic unity alike. Contemptuous of society, he found solace in the natural order
of God’s creation, and nurtured a faith in mankind’s intrinsic innocence. An
awkward mix that coalesced as a singular contention, Rousseau insisted that
religiosity both encouraged and preserved democratic virtue. Was his vision
practicable, much less compelling? Because the unity of his aim so sharply belies the
dissonance of his means, it remains to be seen. Until that point in time we might
summon our courage, and even a bit of faith, as we follow our provocative, peculiar
guide down this thorny path.
35
Chapter 2: The Virtue of Paradox
As Jannes and Jambres opposed Moses, so these men also oppose the truth, men of
corrupt mind and counterfeit faith; but they will not get very far, for their folly will be
plain to all.
—The Second Letter of Paul to Timothy, 3.8,
The New Testament
78
I believe in God quite as strongly as I believe any other truth.
—Rousseau,
Letter to Voltaire
79
A study of Rousseau’s religiosity serves at least three purposes: it sheds light
on his broader philosophic project; it offers a possible means of locating the
consistency he claimed was intrinsic to his works; and it provides a lens through
which to reconsider the relationship between spiritual and secular values. Still, critics
of Rousseau have contended that his collective musings on God, human nature, and
society were of little utility because, taken as a whole, they were neither consistent
nor coherent. Naysayers attributed this failing to our peculiar author’s penchant for
paradox, a charge from which he hardly retreated.
Consider, for example, Rousseau’s request (polite yet insistent) in Book II of
Emile
: “Common
80
readers, pardon me my paradoxes. They are necessary when one
78
2 Timothy 3.8. All Biblical passages not quoted in primary sources are taken from the following
edition:
The New Oxford Annotated Bible, Revised Standard Version
, Herbert G. May and Bruce M.
Metzger, eds. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1973).
79
Letter to Voltaire
, August 18, 1756. OC IV.1071; CW III.117.
80
Rousseau uses the word
vulgaire
, which is understood as
common
when coupled with
reader
. It is
worth noting that
vulgaire
has a more confrontational (and negative) connotation than other, more
familiar word choices, such as
commun
or
ordinaire
.
36
reflects, and no matter what you might say, I prefer to be a man of paradoxes than a
man of prejudices.”
81
Pardon me my paradoxes
. Not even halfway through his massive pedagogical
tome, the Tutor’s confession stands out like a sore thumb; it seems a lot to ask. In
common contemporary usage, paradox often implies contradiction, or even
irreconcilable confusion. Could it be that Rousseau was subverting himself at this
early stage? Was he merely presaging the criticisms of a text whose reception
pressed him into exile for his remaining years? Was it self-deprecation, or brutally
honest self-scrutiny? Should we don investigative caps and uncover the hidden
context? Or must we, common readers, take him at his oft-repeated word to take him
at his word.
Rousseau never claimed to be a virtuous man, and his
Confessions
make clear
an early pattern of less than upright actions. But he did claim to be a good man, a
unique man, and a
consistent and honest
man.
82
Giving him the benefit of the doubt,
and seeking clarity, I turned to the
Oxford English Dictionary
and found this under
Paradox
:
83
81
“Lecteurs vulgaires, pardonnez-moi mes paradoxes. Il en faut faire quand on réfléchit, et quoi que
vous puissiez dire, j’aime mieux être homme à paradoxes qu’homme à préjuges.” OC IV.323; E 93.
82
In his
Letter to Beaumont
, Rousseau applies this consistency to his own defense: “Thus the foolish
public vacillates about me, knowing as little why it detests me as why it liked me before. As for
myself, I have always remained the same: more ardent in my quests, but sincere in everything, even
against myself; simple and good, but sensitive and weak, often doing evil and always loving the
good…” CW IX.22; OC IV.928-9; and: “…all these Books [of mine], which you have read, since
you judge them, breath the same maxims; the same ways (
manières
) of thinking are not more disguised
in them.” OC IV.933; CW IX.26.
83
We might also consider the etymology.
Paradox
comes from the Latin
paradoxum
, from the Greek
paradoxus
, meaning “contrary to received opinion or expectation,” and “past, beyond, contrary to
opinion.” According to Raymond Trousson and Frédéric S. Eigeldinger, the
Encyclopédie
entry for
paradoxe
(penned by d’Alembert) presented a relatively new meaning of the word most frequently in
used in relation to the sciences. This sense implied an “iconoclastic idea, if not heretical, that is to say
a false idea.” In fact, d’Alembert’s definition was more ambiguous: “
en Philosophie
, c'est une
proposition absurde en apparence, à cause qu'elle est contraire aux opinions reçues, & qui néanmoins
37
A statement or tenet contrary to received opinion or belief; often with
the implication that it is marvelous or incredible; sometimes with
unfavourable connotation, as being discordant with what is held to be
established truth, and hence absurd or fantastic; sometimes with
favourable connotation, as a correction of vulgar error.
84
Pardon me my paradoxes
might therefore be rephrased as
pardon me my statements
which stand in contrast to commonly held opinion
.
85
On this—the contrariness and correlative uniqueness of his thought—
Rousseau was certainly consistent. Throughout
Emile
, as in many of his other works,
he reminded us of his opposition to the two major intellectual forces of his age: the
Christian ecclesiasts and the
philosophes
. No meager foes, Church and academy
dominated the production and dissemination of political, social and spiritual thought.
This was no mean feat in a century described then—and, nearly three centuries later,
now—as an age driven by ideas, by the illumination born of inspired reasoning.
est vraie au fond, ou du - moins peut recevoir un air de vérité.” (“
in Philosophy
, it is a seemingly
absurd proposition, because it is contrary to received opinions, & it nevertheless is basically true, or at
least can hold an inkling of truth.”) See: Trousson and Eigeldinger,
Dictionnaire de Jean-Jacques
Rousseau
. (Paris: Honoré Champion Éditeur, 2001), p. 683. For d’Alembert’s definition see: Diderot,
Encyclopédie, ou Dictionnaire Raisonné des Sciences, des Arts, et des Métiers, par une société de gens
de lettres, première édition de 1751-1780
. (Neuchâtel: Chez Samuel Faulche & Compagnie, 1765),
Tome XI, pp. 894-895.
84
The Oxford English Dictionary
. Long before Rousseau, Socrates popularized paradox as a
philosophical method of seeking the truth. Throughout
Emile
, Rousseau affirms the most central
Socratic injunction to “know thyself.” His Socratic lineage is often raised in relation to this Delphic
command. Less frequently mentioned is their common insistence upon the pedagogical value of
paradox—the exercise of contradictory opinion as a means of seeking and uncovering the truth. For
examples of the importance of self-knowledge in
Emile
see: E 48, 74, 83, 213, 240, 243-4, 270, 287.
85
Three French dictionaries confirm this reading. In his 1690
Dictionnaire Universel
, Furetière
describes “paradoxe” as a “[p]roposition surprenant et difficile à croire, à cause qu’elle choque les
opinions communes et reçues.” As examples, he cites the Stoics and Copernicus. The
Grand
Larousse
likewise lists “paradoxe” as both an “[o]pinion contraire aux vues communément admises,”
and (more negatively) as something “qui paraissent défier la logique parce qu’ils présentent en eux-
mêmes des aspects contradictoires.” Hugo’s label of Rousseau—the “Don Quixote of Paradox”—is
attributed to the former sense. The
Dictionnaire historique de la langue française
confirms this less
critical usage in the eighteenth century. Although as early as 1662 Pascal implied that paradoxes
clashed with “good sense” (a charge clearly shared by Rousseau’s critics), this more pejorative
connotation was not formally adopted in dictionaries until 1832. See: Antoine Furetière’s
Dictionnaire
Universel
, Tome III. (The Hague and Rotterdam: Chez Arnout & Reinier Leers, 1690).
Grand
Larousse de la langue française en sept volumes: tome cinquième
. (Paris: Librairie Larousse, 1976), p.
3956.
Dictionnaire historique de la langue française
, Alain Rey, ed. (Paris: Dictionnaires LE
ROBERT, 1992), p. 1422.
38
Contemporary readers may scoff at priests or professors, as purveyors of
pedophilia, or a tweedy clan totally removed from the machinations of real world
politics. But during Rousseau’s age, these men of the cloth and men of letters
wielded an influence far beyond the scope of their professional domains. To attack
either one was a feat of daring, and (because they were mutually antagonistic) a
corresponding proclamation of allegiance to either philosophy or the papacy.
Attacking
both
might have seemed, especially in hindsight, to possess the reckless
energy of a suicidal mission. At the very least, it left so bold a protagonist with few
compatriots.
Such was Rousseau’s fate. The tragedy, the inevitability, the sheer weight of
that ancient term holds particularly true to a thinker for whom truth-telling (as he saw
it) was less an option than an obligation, a destiny, a civic duty.
86
He alone was
poised to tell the truth, because he alone recognized so clearly the problems of and
prescriptions for his age. Urgent necessity underscored Rousseau’s descriptions of
human history’s abject spiral, and his prescriptions for the possible means of our
redemption. By his own admission, he had little choice; our collective future
depended upon bringing these truths to light.
It was this dire term—not personal safety, security, welfare, or reputation—
that drove the Genevan’s quest. Consider this soliloquy, taken from the twelfth
fragment of his
Letter to Christophe de Beaumont
:
86
The compulsive nature of Rousseau’s confessional style notwithstanding, he was deeply ambivalent
about his career as an author. I explore this dynamic elsewhere in greater detail, addressing issues
such as: his epiphany and subsequent “conversion” en route to Vincennes; his insistence that he
defends himself in writing only out of necessity; his elusions to being “forced” to take up his pen; and
his aspiration to abandon writing and the public life for a solitary, self-contained existence. This study
draws much from Jean Starobinski’s reading of Rousseau as a fundamentally passive figure in
Transparency and Obstruction
.
39
My own interest is to say what is useful to others without regard to my
own utility, and that honor which I alone will have among the authors
of my century will always cause me to be distinguished from them all
and will compensate me for all their advantages. If one wishes they
will be better philosophers and finer wits, they will be more profound
thinkers, more precise reasoners, more pleasing writers; but I, I will be
more disinterested in my maxims, more sincere in my sentiments,
more an enemy of satire, bolder in speaking the truth, when it is useful
to others without troubling myself about my fortune nor about my
safety. They may deserve pensions, employments, places in
academies, and I, I will have only insults and slights; they will be
decorated and I, I will be stigmatized, but it does not matter, my
disgraces will honor my courage…
87
Voltaire may revel in his witticisms. Diderot’s plays may delight more people.
Philosophers may enjoy their profundity and sophistication. Others may be honored
in academies and salons, and decorated by their governments. But these gains were
of little concern to Jean-Jacques. He had only his claim to the truth, and the courage
to press this upon a people ‘tyrannized’ by irresponsible élites.
Rousseau’s argument drew upon classical tales of individual courage
legitimized by both resistance to authority and an ascetic aversion to prosperity;
persecution and privation actually offered testimony of his sincerity.
88
In so
defending himself, he resurrected tropes pioneered by Socrates, the Stoics, and the
figure of Jesus. Socrates famously refused compensation for his teachings, and
87
Letter to Beaumont
. OC IV.1022; CW IX.94. The original passage reads: “Mon intérêt à moi est de
dire ce qui est utile aux autres sans égard à ma propre utilité, et cet honneur que j’aurai seul parmi les
auteurs de mon siècle me fera toujours distinguer d’eux tous et me dédommagera de tous leurs
avantages. Ils seront si l’on veut meilleurs philosophes et plus beaux esprits, ils seront penseurs plus
profond[s], raisonneurs plus exacts, écrivains plus agréables ; mais moi je serai plus désintéressé dans
mes maximes, plus sincère dans mes sentiments, plus ennemi de la satire, plus hardi a dire la vérité,
quand elle est utile aux autres sans m’embarrasser de ma fortune ni de ma sûreté. Ils pourront mériter
des pensions, des emplois, des places d’académies et moi je n’aurai que des injures et des affronts ; ils
seront décorés et moi je serai flétri, mais n’importe, mes disgrâces honoreront mon courage…”
88
The word
testimony
has strong Biblical connotations. In Scriptural language, it refers to the Mosaic
Decalogue. See, for example, Exodus 31.18: “And he gave to Moses, when he had made an end of
speaking with him upon Mount Sinai, the two tables of the testimony, tables of stone, written with the
finger of God.”
40
presented his poverty as an exhibit of self-defense during his trial.
89
Seneca and the
Stoics shunned material possessions as a virtuous means of living in greater accord
with nature. And Jesus, Saint Paul revealed, willfully abandoned riches for rags, a
sacrifice committed for the spiritual wealth of his followers.
90
Rousseau made a similar claim. For the sake of his fellow citizens and,
indeed, the human race, he willfully denied his material best-interests. Even if his
own age misunderstood him, in the end he trusted his reputation to the hindsight of
history. His “disgrace will honor his courage” because eventually his paradoxes
would reveal the goodness of his heart, the truthfulness of his writings, the practical
value of his vision, and the short-sightedness of those contemporaries scornful of his
insights.
Truth be told, no matter the cost; his
Confessions
drives this point home,
exposing past episodes of
un
truthfulness in explicit detail. The shame of his
petits
mensonges
are left to public domain, a testament to his honesty even when it reveals a
pattern of
dis
honesty. His second apprenticeship to the engraver M. Ducommun gave
him “vices that I would have hated, such as lying, laziness, theft.”
91
After being
cajoled by a journeyman named Verrat, he commits his first theft, stealing asparagus
and reselling it for pocket change.
92
He reveals an unsavory penchant for flashing
strangers “of the opposite sex” from dark alleys. After one such episode he was
chased down and, upon being caught, attempted to excuse himself by way of a tall
89
See:
The Apology
, 19D-21A in Plato,
The Last Days of Socrates
, Hugh Tredennick, tr. (New York:
Penguin Books, 1969), pp. 48-49.
90
2 Corinthians 2 8.9: “For you know the grace of our Lord Jesus Christ, that though he was rich, yet
for your sake he became poor, so that by his poverty you might become rich.”
91
The Confessions
. CW V.39; OC I.31.
92
The Confessions
. CW V.27-8; OC I.32-33.
41
tale: he claimed to be “a young foreigner of high birth whose brain was deranged.”
93
Most memorably, he forces himself to admit “the long remembrances of crime and
the unbearable weight of remorse with which my conscience is still burdened after
forty years,”
94
the stealing of a pretty pink ribbon whose theft he imputed to a young
innocent, a local girl named Marion.
Ribbons and vegetables, a proclivity for perversity, an adolescent streak of
erratic judgment. A riches of embarrassment, certainly, but necessary to understand
Rousseau as he truly was. His was a heart unmasked, a life laid bare to the public.
His work turned on this principle of honesty: the honesty with which he presents both
himself
and
his age, with which he reveals strengths and weaknesses with equal
candor. Humankind was naturally good, society artificially bad. In so arguing, was
Rousseau not compelled to press this critique upon himself? He too was a good man
guilty of actions with ignoble consequences.
95
To hide such memorable
transgressions would have been, not in poor taste, but in poor faith. Guarding his
missteps would have been, not an act of paradox, but an act of self-subversion that
undermined the very quest to which Rousseau had dedicated his life: to seek and
reveal the truth.
As he wrote unabashedly in
Emile
, “[z]eal and good faith have taken the place
of prudence for me up to now. I hope these guarantors will not abandon me in time
of need. Readers, do not fear from me precautions unworthy of a friend of the truth.
93
The Confessions
. CW V.74-75; OC I.88-90.
94
The Confessions
. CW V.70; OC I.84. For Rousseau’s full account see CW.V 70-73; OC I.84-87.
95
As he makes plain in
The Confessions
, “I have shown myself as I was, contemptible and low when I
was so, good, generous, sublime when I was so.” CW V.5; OC I.V.
42
I shall never forget my motto.”
96
His motto, clipped from Juvenal’s
Satires
, was
Vitam impendere vero
(
Dedicate life to truth
).
97
Truth cast a broad swath indeed, and
took its sharpest stabs when revealing flaws: of his own, of the Church, of the
academy, of human society. This critical acumen proved a costly profession,
particularly for a mere man of the peoples, a Genevan set loose in the hotbed that was
eighteenth century Paris, an expatriate slowed by a urinary tract disorder no less.
Truth be damned, the odds were against him; an individual attacking both papists and
philosophers was bound to lose
something
.
Yet attack he did. Rousseau has been accused of many things by his
compatriots and posthumous critics alike, but cowardly he was not. He targeted
theological and intellectual élites with equal force and candor. Although mutual
enemies, Rousseau charged both with similar offenses: they were deceptive
dogmatists cultivating private interests under the auspices of public good. Both were
grossly self-promoting, driven by vanity and
amour-propre
, rather than a concern
with the welfare of society and
ses peuples
. They were fundamentally dishonest,
preaching salvation through subservience (to either dogma or reason), while
subordinating the welfare of all to exclusive, sectarian interests. Presenting
themselves as above reproach, they deserved our greatest censure.
96
Emile
. E 206.
97
Rousseau also mentions this “motto” in his
Letter to d’Alembert
, the epigraph to
Letters Written
From the Mountain
, and
The Reveries of the Solitary Walker
(Fourth Promenade). Its original context
is quite revealing. The
Satire
in which it appears is a story illustrating the Emperor Domitian’s tyranny
and absurdity. Domitian summons his cringing court to solve a ridiculous problem: how to cook a fish
too large for its pan. We are told that one of these members, Crispus, never spoke out against him and
thus “he survived for eighty winters and as many summers, protected by that armour” of passive
obedience. (IV.92-93) As Juvenal writes, “Crispus never struck out against the current, nor was he
ever that noble type of Roman subject who could freely state his opinions and risk his life for the
truth.” (IV.89-91) In adopting this last line as his motto, Rousseau identifies himself precisely with the
“noble” citizen who
would
—and did—risk personal livelihood “for the truth.” See: Juvenal,
The
Satires
, Niall Rudd, tr. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), p. 28.
43
The Church, for example, taught a “barbarous education which sacrifices the
present to an uncertain future, which burdens a child with chains of every sort and
begins by making him miserable in order to prepare him from afar for I know not
what pretended happiness which is to be believed he will never enjoy.”
98
With their
“insipid lessons,” “long-winded moralizing,” and “eternal catechisms,”
99
they
promoted a “false wisdom which incessantly projects us outside of ourselves, which
always counts the present for nothing, and which, pursuing without respite a future
that retreats in proportion as we advance, by dint of transporting us where we are not,
transports us where we shall never be.”
100
The chimera of post-mortem redemption
lures us to seek an ever-elusive salvation. In the process, it discourages the
possibility of genuine reform and salvation in
this
world, instead fixing our gaze on
an indeterminate future while chaining us to a grim present.
Philosophers were no better. “Raised in all the corruption of the colleges,”
101
enraptured by their own hubris,
102
their vanity and pride was no less pernicious than
that of their orthodox enemies. “Where,” Rousseau asked, “is the philosopher who
would not gladly deliver mankind for his own glory? Where is the one who in the
secrecy of his heart sets himself any other goal than that of distinguishing
himself?”
103
His contemporary
hommes à lettres
claimed to possess truth, but taught
only vainglory. “Under the haughty pretext that they alone are enlightened, true, and
of good faith, they imperiously subject us to their peremptory decisions and claim to
98
Emile
. E 79.
99
Emile
. E 316.
100
Emile
. E 79.
101
Emile
. E 221.
102
“I know of no philosopher who has yet been so bold as to say: this is the limit of what man can
attain and beyond which he cannot go. We do not know what our nature permits us to be.” (
Emile
. E
62.)
103
Emile
. E 269.
44
give us as the true principles of things the unintelligible systems they have built in
their imagination.”
104
Their purported truths were elaborate feats of fancy whose
want of substance was rivaled only by a conspicuous incoherence. Philosophic
perfectionism mixed Spartan coercion and Athenian frivolousness, to decidedly
deleterious consequences. Rather than aiding society, they increased the speed of its
downfall. Rather than putting their erudition and learning to practical purposes, they
wasted their time (and ours) on vain frivolities.
The church and the academy were, in short, two birds of a feather. “The two
parties attack each other reciprocally with so many sophisms,” yet neither fostered
virtue, goodness or meaningful enlightenment.
105
Put more strongly, they actually
caused much harm. Both falsely claimed to possess a monopoly on truth, and used
this self-anointed grace to subject humankind to the tyranny of elaborately justified
opinions. Peddling ideals unfulfilled in practice, priest and philosopher alike
demanded contrition to hollow promises. As such, they epitomized society’s most
perverse influence: the denaturing rule of
doxa
.
It was a story of muses whose lulling tunes promise big payoff but lead to
swift demise. Jean-Jacques ignored their refrains, and refused to bow to their
authority. Instead, he countered with paradox in its sharpest form: a severe mistrust
of these dominant poles of opinion whose empires—Christian dogmatism and
philosophic rationalism—were enemies of truth and societal welfare alike.
To better gauge Rousseau’s request of pardon, we must therefore bear in mind
the contentious nature of his paradoxes, and the vigorous charges he levies against the
104
Emile
. E 312.
105
Emile
. E, 312n.
45
established “truths,” and so-called truth-tellers, of his age. To pardon Rousseau, we
must first accept the substance of his accusations. Doing so, in turn, requires
acknowledging his candid evaluations of his influential adversaries. Forgiveness in
this instance is an act of solidarity. Rousseau demands not simply siding with him
(both the “honest” author and the “good” man), but rejecting the targets of his wrath.
Rousseau was perhaps the most famous to press this demand upon his readers,
but certainly not the first. His much-maligned foil Hobbes said just as much in 1656,
in a moment of aggressive self-defense. In 1645, Hobbes and the Anglican Bishop
John Bramhall, both Royalists forced into exile during the Civil War, were invited by
William Cavendish, the Marquess of Newcastle, to debate the question of human
freedom at his Paris home. These discussions led to the publication some nineteen
years later of Hobbes’
The Questions Concerning Liberty, Necessity, and Chance
. In
this work, Hobbes railed against Bramhall and linguistic ignorance in one fell swoop:
The Bishop speaks often of Paradoxes with such scorn or detestation,
that a simple Reader would take a Paradox either for Felony, or some
other heinous crime, or else for some ridiculous turpitude; whereas
perhaps a Judicious Reader knows what the word signifies; And that a
Paradox, is an opinion not yet generally received.
106
“Simple” readers conflate paradox with unpardonable offense. The more “judicious”
exercise greater restraint in judgment. They understand that paradoxes are
unfashionable, but not necessarily erroneous.
To punctuate this point, Hobbes reminds us that even “Christian religion was
once a Paradox.”
107
Historically, he is correct. As Karl Jaspers argued, although “it
is not possible to base a portrait of Jesus on compelling historic proof, his reality is
106
Thomas Hobbes,
The Questions Concerning Liberty, Necessity, and Chance
. (London: Printed for
Andrew Crook, 1656), p. 239.
107
Ibid., p. 239.
46
clearly discernible through the veil of tradition.”
108
For reasons unclear, we know
that Jesus did in fact go to Jerusalem preaching what were then paradoxes, and was
crucified for his teachings.
109
Hobbes’ reminder is twofold: popular opinion is fallible and relative in
character, and contrary opinions may be redeemed in time. Nonconformity
demonized in one age or locale can pass for gospel in another. In fact, canonization
and martyrdom occur
only
through the passage of time (through reification). This is
particularly true of Christianity, a phenomenon whose appreciation emerged in
hindsight, and drew legitimacy from its resistance to the remarkable hostility with
which it was first received. What was once paradox, what once begged a sentence of
death, became the most wildly influential spiritual, political and intellectual force of
Hobbes’ realm.
Again, the lesson is simple: paradoxes are relative by definition. They are
measured in relation to temporal opinion, rather than objective standards of truth or
virtue. Although paradoxes run contrary to general opinion, they are neither
inherently ill-conceived, nor categorically criminal. Yet for Rousseau, this distinction
was moot. As with Jesus, the Genevan’s paradoxes
did
criminalize him, particularly
following the publication of
Emile
. And here, Hobbes’ example sounds a powerful
108
Karl Jaspers,
Socrates, Buddha, Confucius, Jesus: The Paradigmatic Individuals
, Hannah Arendt,
ed. and Ralph Manheim, tr. (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1962), p. 64. Jaspers also
demonstrates the relative unimportance of historic accuracy to Christian believers, a point compatible
with Rousseau’s own appreciation of myth. (See pp. 64-86.) For an extended discussion of this theme
in Rousseau’s works, see below.
109
“This God who for Jesus was not physically present—not in visions and not in voices—was able to
put absolutely everything in the world in question,” Jaspers writes. The consequences were radically
contrary: “Jesus broke free from every practical order in the world. He saw that all orders and habits
had become pharisaical; he points to the source in which they melt to nothingness. All earthly reality
is deprived of its foundation, absolutely and definitively. All orders whatsoever, the bonds of piety, of
law, of reasonable custom, collapse.” Humankind kind is left only with the absolute imperative “to
follow God into the kingdom of heaven.” See: Jaspers, p. 79.
47
note. The once-hunted—Christian religion—had become the hunter; Jean-Jacques,
condemned for impiety, was its prey.
* * * * *
Rousseau should have known better. Evidence suggests that he in fact did. In
Fragment VII of
Institutions politiques
,
110
“Luxury, Commerce, and the Arts,” he
admitted that “I have learned through experience the damage that demonstrated
propositions can suffer from being called Paradoxes.”
111
Rousseau was referring to
the abundant criticism that followed the publication of his
Discourses
. As Genevan
naturalist Charles Bonnet (under the antagonistic pseudonym M. Philopolis, or “Mr.
City-lover”) wrote in a letter dated August 25, 1755, Jean-Jacques “has adopted ideas
that seem to me so opposed to the truth and so ill suited to make happy people” that
“[m]uch will, without doubt, be written against this new Discourse, as much has been
written against the one that won the prize of the Academy of Dijon.”
112
Rousseau
paraded banners of natural goodness and truth, but presented only misery and
falsehoods. This was “a paradox that he has cherished only too much.”
113
In closing,
110
In its preface, Rousseau describes
The Social Contract
as a “short treatise… taken from a more
extensive work, which I undertook in the past without considering my strength, and have long since
abandoned.” (
Social Contract
. CW IV.131; OC III.349). The “more extensive work” was his
intended masterpiece,
Institutions politiques
. Rousseau began writing this unfinished work sometime
between 1754 and 1759. Fragment VII was likely written no earlier than 1756, and no later than 1758.
This would place its composition after the publication of the
Second Discourse
, and before the
publication of the
Letter to d’Alembert
. For Rousseau’s description see:
The Confessions
. CW V.340-
341; OC I.404-405.
111
Political Fragments
. CW IV.46; OC III.518.
112
Letter from M. Philopolis on the Subject of the Discourse of M. J.-J. Rousseau of Geneva on the
Origin and Foundations of Inequality among Men
. CW III.123; OC III.1383.
113
Letter from M. Philopolis
. CW III.123; OC III.1383.
48
Bonnet struck an incredulous note: “Had we ever presumed that a Writer who thinks,
would advance in a century like ours this strange paradox”?
114
According to Bonnet, Jean-Jacques was a depressing rabble-rouser, his
writings desolate tirades, and his inexplicable contrariness an affect to garner
attention.
115
Rousseau bristled at the charges. He was particularly upset with the
implication that his paradoxes were falsehoods, and perverse sources of personal
pride. “Let us suppose,” he wrote in rebuttal, “that a singular mind (
esprit
), bizarre,
and in fact
a man of paradoxes
, then dared to reproach others for the absurdity of
their maxims, to prove to them that they run to death in seeking tranquility, that by
dint of being reasonable they do nothing but ramble.”
116
The note of pardon struck later in
Emile
here smacks of indignation.
Rousseau the contrary, Rousseau the unique, was merely holding his peers
accountable for the “absurdity” of their “ramblings.” At this early date he was
conscious of the practical dangers of writing paradox; he simply threw caution to the
wind. The truth of
one
was all the more important considering the falsehoods of
many
. Drawing courage from faith in his own truthfulness, Rousseau was firmly
convinced that his contemporaries were in the wrong. Their maxims posed the
philosophical equivalent of lemmings, leading us from steep cliffs towards
accelerated demise. His
Discourses
offered an alternate path to tread.
114
Letter from M. Philopolis
. “Eût-on jamais présumé qu’un Écrivain qui pense, avanceroit dans un
siècle tel que le nôtre cet étrange paradoxe, qui renferme seul une si grande foule d’inconséquences,
pour ne rien dire de plus fort ?” OC III.1385; CW III.125.
115
This follows Diderot’s charge that Rousseau had reversed his position on the arts and sciences,
implying that a critical stance would garner more attention than an affirmative case.
116
Letter from J.-J. Rousseau to M. Philopolis
. OC.III.231; CW III.127. (My emphasis.)
49
In asking pardon some years later, Rousseau softened his tone—though not
his resolve. Still convinced of the value of his contentiousness, he turned to readers
for reprieve. Demanding that we pardon him his paradoxes, Jean-Jacques was
certainly begging an important question; he was just asking it of the wrong people.
“Common readers” were clearly not his most pointed critics. In the years
following his exchange with Bonnet,
Julie
became the best-selling novel of the
eighteenth century.
117
Le Devin du village
, an opera composed in the Italian style,
opened in Fontainebleu to a stunningly positive reception. In spite of unequivocal
censure and censoring,
Emile
was widely read and followed (to the extent that
breastfeeding became
très chic
amongst French mothers). And his
Social Contract
was embraced as far as Poland, for whose government he wrote a commissioned
piece on political reform.
Although Rousseau’s influential detractors multiplied their protests following
his 1762 publications,
118
evidence in the form of letters suggest that the public had
not yet followed suit. On June 15, 1762, d’Alembert wrote Rousseau to assure him
that the French peoples applauded his controversial writings.
119
And one day later,
Genevan minister Paul-Claude Moultou comforted his friend that a majority of his
117
Robert Darnton labeled
Julie
Rousseau’s “supreme best-seller.”
The Forbidden Best-Sellers of Pre-
Revolutionary France
, (New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 1995), p. 66.
118
Namely,
The Social Contract
and
Emile
.
119
Raymond Trousson and Frédéric S. Eigeldinger,
Rousseau au jour le jour: Chronologie
. (Paris:
Honoré Champion Éditeur, 1998), p. 172. Notably, d’Alembert was the only
philosophe
to offer such
support, save Charles Duclos. In
The Confessions
, Rousseau seems characteristically ungrateful,
underscoring the fact that d’Alembert had not signed the letter. For Rousseau’s account see:
The
Confessions
, OC I.574; CW V.480. Quoted in Maurice Cranston,
The Solitary Self: Jean-Jacques
Rousseau in Exile and Adversity
. (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), pp. 2-3. Letter
appears in CC XI.1874.82-84.
50
fellow Swiss (“
nos bourgeois
”) admired
The Social Contract
as the “arsenal of
liberty.”
120
Common readers were certainly far more forgiving than the subjects of his
scorn. Rousseau’s intellectual peers, a proud lot of atheists and anti-Clericalists,
might have been more supportive had he not already alienated and infuriated them.
His friendship with Diderot deteriorated over a controversy dating from 1757. In his
play
Le fils naturel
, Diderot attacks the idea of a solitary individual (whose part is
played by Dorval, a character based on Rousseau) with a line much to Jean-Jacques’
disliking: “il n' y a que le méchant qui soit seul.”
121
On August 30, 1755, Voltaire
wrote a letter to Rousseau in which he described the
Second Discourse
as a “book
against the human race.”
122
Voltaire sounds both hostile and dumbfounded, quipping
that “[n]ever has so much intelligence been used in seeking to make us stupid.”
123
Following Rousseau’s
Letter to d’Alembert
(denouncing a proposed Genevan theater)
nearly three years later, Voltaire wrote his
own
letter to d’Alembert dismissing
Rousseau as “a Diogène barking.”
124
“There is a double ingratitude in him,” Voltaire
120
“Nos bourgeois n’en disent pas moins que ce
Contrat social
est l’arsenal de la liberté, et tandis
qu’un petit nombre jette feu & flammes, la multitude triomphe.”
Le minister Paul-Claude Moultou à
Rousseau
. CC XI.1877.90.
121
The full sentence is actually quite inflammatory. Diderot’s character Constance uses a Rousseauist
argument (an ‘appeal to the heart’) to convince Dorval that the “good man” exists only in society: “
J'en appelle à votre coeur; interrogez-le; et il vous dira que l'homme de bien est dans la société, et qu' il
n' y a que le méchant qui soit seul.” From
Le fils naturel
, Act IV, Scene 3. In:
Diderot: Œuvres
,
Tome
IV: Esthétique – Théâtre
, Laurent Versini, ed. (Paris: Éditions Robert Laffont, S.A., 1996), p. 1113.
For Rousseau’s reaction to this “scathing and harsh sentence without any qualification,” see:
The
Confessions
. CW V.382; OC I.455.
122
Letter from Voltaire to Rousseau
(August 30, 1755). CW III.102; CC III.317.156.
123
Letter from Voltaire to Rousseau
(August 30, 1755). CW III.102; CC III.317.157. Voltaire’s
sentence reads: “On n’a jamais tant employé d’esprit a vouloir nous rendre Bêtes.”
124
Quoted in Cranston,
The Noble Savage: Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 1754-1762
. (Chicago: The
University of Chicago Press, 1991), p. 137. Voltaire here compares Rousseau to Diogenes the Cynic,
one of the most colorful figures in the history of Greek philosophy. An exile himself (from his native
Sinope), Diogenes’ practice of Cynicism was notably flamboyant. Embracing hardship as a training
method for self-sufficiency, he earned an (in)famous reputation for spectacles such as public
masturbation, begging to statues, and sleeping in hard tubs. He was often described as a “mad dog”
51
continued. “He attacks an art which he practices himself, and he has written against
you, who have overwhelmed him with praises.”
125
Years later, Rousseau’s reputation
as an ingrate magnified. Retreating from the continent following the furor of 1762,
he even managed to enrage his host, the notoriously mild-mannered Hume, who
vilified him as “the blackest and most atrocious villain, beyond comparison, that now
exists in the world.”
126
If Rousseau’s personality incensed his peers, his paradoxes—particularly
those detailed in
The Profession of Faith of a Savoyard Vicar
—aroused the wrath of
Church and state alike. Despite his fame as an author throughout Europe, official
critics in France and Geneva greeted his 1762 publications with swift orders of
interdiction. In Moultou’s same June 16 letter pledging Swiss popular support, he
also warned Rousseau that the Petit Conseil had banned
The Social Contract
and
begun a formal investigation of
Emile
.
127
The news came as no surprise. One week prior, on June 9, the French
Parlement had issued a warrant for his arrest. The Genevan was charged with
penning a work of “impious and detestable principles” contemptuous of religion,
and a “Socrates gone mad.” See: Diogenes Laertius,
Lives of Eminent Philosophers: Volume II
, pp.
23-85.
125
Quoted in Ibid., p. 137. Voltaire vigorously repeated these charges in a subsequent letter to
d’Alembert. (See Ibid., p. 278). These correspondences followed his biting (and very personal)
attacks on
Julie
and its author, written under the pseudonym Marquis de Ximénès. See:
Lettres à M.
de Voltaire sur La Nouvelle Héloïse
(Geneva: 1761, 25 pages
in octavio
).
126
Quoted in Cranston,
The Solitary Self
, 168. In leaving England, Rousseau also rejected the one
hundred pound yearly pension granted him by King George III. For a concise exposition of the sudden
demise of the relationship between Rousseau and Hume, see pp. 165-169. See also: Edward Duffy,
Rousseau in England: The Context for Shelley’s Critique of the Enlightenment
. (Berkeley: University
of California Press, 1979).
127
Moultou à Rousseau
. CC XI.1877.90. Dates confirmed in Trousson and Eigeldinger,
Rousseau au
jour le jour
, p. 172. The works were formally investigated, beginning on June 11, 1762. By June 14,
both were officially deemed “very dangerous.” See: James Miller,
Rousseau: Dreamer of Democracy
,
pp. 81-82.
52
Church and King alike.
128
The court order condemned him as a blasphemer “who
subjects Religion to the examination of reason, who establishes nothing but a purely
human faith, and who accepts neither truths nor dogmas in the matter of Religion.”
129
Adding insult to impiety, Rousseau also asserted “propositions which tend to give a
false and odious character to the sovereign authority, to destroy the principle of
obedience due to him, and to weaken the respect and the love of the People for their
King.”
130
Rousseau had struck a passionate nerve, one not easily calmed. Nearly three
months later, on August 28, Archduke Christophe de Beaumont continued the robust
denouncement. In a Pastoral Letter, he condemned
Emile
for
containing an abominable doctrine, suited to overturning natural Law
and to destroying the foundations of the Christian Religion;
establishing maxims contrary to Evangelical morality; tending to
disturb the peace of States, to stir up Subjects against the authority of
their Sovereign; as containing a very great number of propositions
respectively false, scandalous, full of hatred against the Church and its
Ministers, departing from the respect due to Sacred Scripture and the
Tradition of the Church, erroneous, impious, blasphemous, and
heretical.
131
Beaumont described the work’s author as “a character given to paradoxes of opinions
and conduct, zeal for ancient maxims with the rage for establishing novelties, the
obscurity of retreat with the desire to be known by everyone.”
132
The ensuing order
128
These quotes appear in the
Extrait des Registres du Parlement
,
Arrêt de la cour de Parlement
,
Qui
condamne un Imprimé ayant pour titre Émile
,
ou de l’Éducation
,
par J. J. Rousseau
,
imprimé à La
Hage… M.DCC.LXII
.,
à être lacéré & brûlé par l’Exécuteur de la Haute Justice
. The text is
reproduced in the beginning of Rousseau’s
Letter to Beaumont
, 1763 edition. See:
Jean-Jacques
Rousseau, Citoyen à Genève, à Christophe de Beaumont, Archevêque de Paris, Duc de St. Cloud, Pair
de France, Commandeur de l’Ordre du St. Esprit, Proviseur de Sorbonne, &c
. (Amsterdam: Chez
Marc Michel Rey, 1763). See also: CC XI.A254.262-266.
129
Ibid.
130
Ibid.
131
Pastoral Letter of His Grace, the Archbishop of Paris
. CW IX.16.
132
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.4.
53
of contraband reiterated what the Parlement had previously made plain.
Emile
was a
work deeply threatening to the very fabrics of eighteenth century order. It was
immoral, revolutionary, hateful, and fundamentally
wrong
. Rousseau’s “paradoxes”
were irresolvable contradictions, the public ravings of a supposedly solitary
individual who evoked traditionalism in the service of its own destruction. They also
carried the stigma of a communicable disease: not only were they offensive, they
would infect the masses with dreams of overthrowing Church and Sovereign alike. A
work of imminent danger, its distribution had to be stopped, its author held
accountable.
It should now be clear why Maurice Cranston describes, without exaggeration,
this latter third of Jean-Jacques’ life as a period of “exile and adversity.”
133
Woody
Allen once dubbed paranoia another word for realism; for Rousseau, the hostile
suspicion which swelled within him after 1762 was rooted in an all-too-real
persecution waged on theological, political and intellectual fronts.
Given this turn of events, Rousseau’s request of pardon in
Emile
seems
particularly prescient and all the more compelling. As contemporary readers armed
with historical hindsight, we are surely poised to grant him reprieve. Still, before
doing so we must answer two questions: what, specifically, were the theological and
political paradoxes put forth, and why were they necessary to his thought, as he so
forthrightly claimed?
* * * * *
133
Cranston,
The Solitary Self: Jean-Jacques Rousseau in Exile and Adversity
.
54
Emile
holds the dubious distinction of being Rousseau’s most controversial
book. Burned and banned for impiousness in 1762, critics were especially incensed
by its third-person
Profession of Faith of the Savoyard Vicar
. A substantial section of
Book IV, this deistic sermon preached two particularly unpopular paradoxes: the
pressing need for religious tolerance, and the Pelagian heresy that man was naturally
innocent. If these proved to be Rousseau’s most threatening ideas, their exposition
was not without precedent. He had argued analogous points eight years prior in the
Discourse on Inequality
. Presented as searing socio-political critique, Rousseau’s
Second Discourse
tempered a deeply critical genealogy of human history with the
radical optimism of a doctrine of natural goodness.
Even then, Rousseau understood the dangers in making such claims. He
began the
Discourse
with a declaration of courage: the questions raised within its
pages were “not proposed by those who are afraid of honoring the truth.”
134
The
Genevan had no such fear; but to honor
veritas
, he first abandoned the facts.
135
Without a hint of irony, he urged his readers to follow him, to
begin by setting all the facts aside, for they do not affect the question.
The Researches which can be undertaken concerning this Subject must
not be taken for historical truths, but only for hypothetical and
conditional reasonings better suited to clarify the Nature of things than
to show their genuine origin.
136
Rousseau’s logic here offers yet another paradox, a rejoinder to the scientific method
popularized by his Enlightenment peers. But it also reflects a methodology privileged
134
Second Discourse
. CW III.18; OC III.131.
135
By contrast, Bloom writes that in
Emile
, “Rousseau banishes poetry altogether and suppresses all
lies.” (E 8) As noted above, this is not entirely accurate. Rousseau was, indeed, a self-proclaimed
“friend of truth.” But his relationship with the arts and fiction reflects deep ambivalence rather than
categorical condemnation. Rousseau clearly appreciates arts which serve a specific social function
(such as the education of virtue).
136
Second Discourse
. CW III.19; OC III.132-133.
55
throughout his works: namely, the use of subjective memory in writing political
philosophy. The clearest example is that of his autobiography. Halfway through the
text Rousseau himself reminded us that the “first part [of
The Confessions
] was
written entirely from memory and I must have made many errors in it. Forced to
write the second from memory also, I will probably make many more.”
137
Recent
scholarship has confirmed greater historical accuracy than Jean-Jacques would have
us believe, yet the discrepancies to which he drew our attention have been verified.
138
Even more dramatically, scholars have described in detail the dissonance between
Rousseau’s ideal vision of Geneva and the city in practice in works such as
Letters
Written From the Mountain
,
Letter to d’Alembert
,
La Nouvelle Héloïse,
and the
dedicatory epistle to the
Second Discourse
.
139
For Rousseau, these inaccuracies actually served a distinct purpose. As he
reiterated in
Emile
, facts are not always useful in teaching virtue. He gleaned this
lesson from ancient Pagan histories, epic works of men like Plutarch “filled with
views which one could use even if the facts which present them were false.”
140
His
age, by contrast, ignored the vitality of this lesson. “Critical erudition absorbs
everything, as if it were very important whether a fact is true, provided that a useful
teaching can be drawn from it.”
141
In their haste to compile and systematize
knowledge, the encyclopedic
lumières
discounted the pedagogical value of fabled
137
The Confessions
. CW V.233; OC I.277.
138
By far the most impressive of such efforts is Raymond Trousson and Frédéric S. Eigeldinger,
Rousseau au jour le jour: Chronologie
. Although certainly not aligned with the spirit Rousseau here
articulates, the
Chronologie
is a remarkable feat of scholarship tracing nearly every day in the life of
Jean-Jacques, and detailing what he did, where he went, and with whom he corresponded.
139
See: Miller,
Rousseau: Dreamer of Democracy
, pp. 93-96; Benjamin Barber, “How Swiss is
Rousseau?”
Political Theory
, Vol. 13, No. 4, November 1985.
140
Emile
. E 156; OC IV.415.
141
Emile
. E 156; OC IV.415.
56
histories. Unlike the dissemination of cold facts, tales of glorious deeds—of Spartan
rigor, of Robinson Crusoe’s self-sufficiency
142
—serve the most noble of aims: they
lead by example, allowing us to revel in reveries of greatness. “Critical erudition”
might enhance our knowledge of science or refine philosophic discourse, but it
contributes little to the subject of instituting virtue amongst individuals in a corrupted
society.
143
Such was the scope of Rousseau’s ambition. By his own admission, education
had less to do with child-rearing than the pursuit of a more enlightened social order.
Rousseau reiterated this point in the
Letters Written From the Mountain
, insisting that
“[i]t is a question of a new system of education the plan of which I offer to the
examination of the wise, and not of a method for fathers and mothers, about which I
never dreamed.”
144
Emile
—like Plato’s
Republic
—taught us how to reclaim virtue amidst a
society in decline. Rousseau pointed us towards this very connection in Book I: “Do
you want to get an idea of public education? Read Plato’s
Republic
. It is not at all a
political work, as think those who judge books only by their titles. It is the most
142
Rousseau makes countless glowing references to Sparta throughout his works.
Robinson Crusoe
,
the story of solitary virtue
par excellence
, is the first and only book Emile reads: “Since we absolutely
must have books, there exists one which, to my taste, provides the most felicitous treatise on natural
education. This book will be the first that my Emile will read… What, them, is this marvelous book?
Is it Aristotle? Is it Pliny? Is it Buffon? No. It is
Robinson Crusoe
.” E 184; OC IV.454-455.
143
Rousseau uses this standard of general merit in his own defense in
Letters Written From the
Mountain
. “My God, what would happen if, in a great work full of useful truths, lessons of humanity,
piety, and virtue, one was allowed to go looking with a malicious precision for all the errors, all the
equivocal, suspect, or ill-considered propositions, all the inconsistencies that amid the detail can elude
an Author overburdened with his material, overwhelmed by the numerous ideas it suggests to him,
distracted from some by the others, and who can hardly assemble in his head all the parts of his vast
plan?” Even the Gospel, Rousseau concludes, would fare poorly in the face of such “slanderous
analysis.” CW IX.150-151; OC III.708-709. From a moral standpoint, intent is more significant than
execution. As Rousseau writes in the
Reveries
(Fourth Promenade), “Only the intention of the speaker
gives them their worth and determines their degree of malice or goodness.” CW VIII.32; OC I.1029.
144
Letters Written From the Mountain
(Fifth Letter). CW IX.211; OC III.783.
57
beautiful educational treatise ever written.”
145
As in
Emile
, Plato presented a model
of how to live virtuously. And like Rousseau, he employed myth to teach this
difficult lesson.
146
Methodology notwithstanding, Socrates opened Book X of the
Republic
by
emphasizing the dangers of poetry.
Poesis
, he reminded us, was misleading; it
provided only seductive simulacrums of ideal forms. Even the works of “tragic
poets… seem to maim the thought of those who hear them and do not as a remedy
have the knowledge of how they really are.”
147
Socrates’ objection echoed his belief
that philosophers must always prefer true wisdom to a pale or distorted shade;
anything less, particularly an imitative art, distracts us from our pursuit of the good.
For Socrates, “[t]he maker of the phantom, the imitator” was essentially
superficial; he “understands nothing of what is but rather of what looks like it is.”
148
Imitation was a form of “wizardry”; it ruled from the throne of
doxa
, tended towards
imprudence, and reflected a fundamental disunity of the soul (the dissonance between
reality and appearance).
149
Poetry was also dangerous because it unleashed excessive
spiritedness: “we give ourselves over to following the imitation; suffering along with
145
Emile
. E 40.
146
In the
Laws
, Plato’s Athenian counters those who “opine that the gods exist, but scorn and neglect
human affairs.” (900b) Against “him who loves to censure the gods for neglect,” he first uses force
before conceding that “he needs also, as it seems to me, some words of counsel to act as a charm upon
him.” (903b) To do so, the Athenian evokes Odysseus and the myth of transported souls to illustrate
his lesson. Myth here plays a vital role in the philosophic education, persuading where force alone
cannot. (903b-905d) See: Plato,
Laws
, R. G. Bury, tr. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1926),
pp. 353, 363-371. See also: Miller,
Rousseau: Dreamer of Democracy
, pp. 92-104.
147
The Republic
X.595b. (Bloom 277) All quotes are taken from: Plato,
The Republic of Plato
,
Second
Edition
, Allan Bloom, tr. (New York: Basic Books, 1968 & 1991).
148
The Republic
X.601b (Bloom 284).
149
See:
The Republic
X.602d, 603a-c. (Bloom 285-287).
58
the hero in all seriousness, we praise as a good poet the man who most puts us in this
state.”
150
The Athenian sage seemed to draw a Manichaean line. Yet immediately after,
he introduces Homer
151
as neither a philosopher nor an imitator, but a class in-
between “able to recognize what sorts of practices make human beings better or
worse in private and in public.”
152
Homer is redeemed from the status of phantom-
menace because he both understood and
taught
virtuous conduct: “it is told that
Homer, while he was himself alive, was in private a leader for education for certain
men who cherished him for his intercourse and handed down a certain Homeric way
of life to those who came after.”
153
His art possessed normative value because it
lighted the path to pursue higher goods.
Rousseau’s simultaneous (and at face value, awkward) embrace of truth and
‘dismissal’ of facts fulfils a similar purpose. For Rousseau, pseudo-fictionalized
histories conjured visions of
possible
virtue unrealized in his modern world. Tales of
inspired heroism, epic wisdom, or ideal polities offered heuristic models that both
inspired appreciation and urged action.
154
Socrates—and, for that matter, the poetic Plato—demonstrated this dynamic
by evoking the myth of Er. The latter part of
Republic’s
Book X recounts this fable
150
The Republic
X.605d (Bloom 289).
151
This follows Socrates’ condemnation of Homer in Book II: “we mustn’t accept Homer’s—or any
other poet’s—foolishly making this mistake about the gods” being “the cause of everything” for
humans. See:
The Republic
II.379c-d (Bloom 57).
152
The Republic
X.599d (Bloom 282).
153
Plato adds that “Pythagoras himself was particularly cherished for this reason, and his successors
even now still give Pythagoras’ name to a way of life that makes them seem somehow outstanding
among men.”
The Republic
X.600a (Bloom 283).
154
Furthermore, Rousseau believes such fictions to possess meaningful truths. “Fictions which have a
moral purpose are called allegories or fables; and as their purpose is or ought to be only to wrap useful
truths in easily perceived and pleasing forms, in such cases we hardly care about hiding the
de facto
lie, which is only the cloak of truth; and he who merely sets forth a fable as a fable in no way lies.”
Reveries
(Fourth Promenade). CW VIII.32; OC I.1029.
59
of a warrior’s descent into a demonic place where souls must choose hosts to inhabit.
Odysseus, remembering the honor of past deeds, wisely claims “the life of a private
man who minds his own business.”
155
This story is one of redemption that
demonstrates through allegory the significance of sound judgment in both this and the
next life.
156
Socrates’ company learns a persuasive lesson of agency—“[t]he blame
belongs to him who chooses, god is blameless”
157
—and are reminded of mankind’s
challenge “always to choose the better from among those that are possible.”
158
In so
doing, Odysseus demonstrates the practical benefits of wisdom and the eternal
repercussions of choice.
Regardless of the facts, the myth is useful if the lesson holds. As Socrates
tells Glaucon, “a tale was saved and not lost; and it could save us, if we were
persuaded by it, and we shall make a good crossing of the river of Lethe and not
defile our soul.”
159
Rousseau was perhaps more concerned with this life than the
next,
160
but the point he undoubtedly drew from the
Republic
stands: parable can offer
a powerful tool of learning.
161
Unlike poetry for Plato, or theater and the hollow speech of
philosophes
, Jean-
Jacque’s historical conjecture serves a practical and virtuous aim: an education
committed to social transformation.
Reverie
acts as a heuristic device, a pseudo-
fictional means of posing both clear and present problems (our history of decline) and
155
The Republic
X 620c (Bloom 303).
156
It is worth noting that Rousseau also accepted the immortality of the soul.
157
The Republic
X.617e (Bloom 300).
158
The Republic
X.618b-c (Bloom 301).
159
The Republic
X.621b-c (Bloom 303).
160
We must, however, bear in mind that Rousseau placed increasing faith in future redemption as the
persecution of his works and person increased: in an afterlife, in the annals of history, from readers.
As we will later see, this was particularly evident in his posthumously-published
Reveries
.
161
Readers should compare this position to Rousseau’s assessment of the arts in his
Letter to
d’Alembert
and the
First Discourse
..
60
viable solutions (sociopolitical reform). Epic histories encourage a process of
discovery and improvement by painting vivid canvasses of how life
might have been
and how it
ought to be
. In Rousseau’s own works, this dual purpose serves a single
end: teaching humankind to enact a better future as both individuals and citizens.
162
As he writes near the end of
Emile
, if “[t]he golden age is treated as a chimera,…
What, then, would be required to give it a new birth? One single but impossible
thing: to love it.”
163
Such love—of our fellow citizens, of society, of mankind’s
future—begins precisely with the courage to dream the virtuous dream.
At this point, skeptical readers may charge Rousseau with the very crimes he
imputes to theologians and academicians. If his philosophical musings indeed present
“a reality to be encountered, experienced, and savored,”
164
why are they not also
guilty of vain or misguided perfectionism? The answer lies in an indelicate balance.
If Rousseau embraces myth as a form of pedagogy, his idealized images—of Geneva,
162
Judith Shklar takes a grim view of Rousseau’s worldview, one which she believes “offers no
occasion for happiness or civic virtue.” Shklar ends her book with this overstatement: “When he
called upon his readers to choose between man and the citizen he was forcing them to face the moral
realities of social life. They were asked, in fact, not to choose, but to recognize that the choice was
impossible, and that they were not and would never become either men or citizens.” (p. 214) This is
misleading in two significant ways. First, Rousseau’s concept of moral individualism is coterminous
with society in the sense that morality is nonexistent in the state of nature. The duties and relations
born of citizenship constrict and pervert individual goodness, particularly in large cosmopolitan cities
such as Athens and Paris. But Rousseau’s vision of virtue also finds fruition within societies—whether
those of quaint Geneva, or the self-contained community under Wolmar’s watchful eye (in
Julie
), or
through the general will. His attempt to apply
The Social Contract
to the politically-challenged nation
of Poland also illustrates an effort to institute a greater measure of virtue under less-than-ideal
conditions. Still, in her
Appendix
, Shklar notes the dismal failures of Emile and Sophie to reenter
society in
Les Solitaires
: “The happy end of
Emile
is false,… and Emile’s character cannot reveal itself
until he
really
becomes a man, that is, a suffering victim.” (p. 235) Again, it is hard to argue against
the extreme difficulty of living virtuously within society. It is quite another thing to take this as
evidence that Rousseau condemns the human condition to one of permanent, necessary suffering. At
the very least, readers must reconcile this conclusion with the abject optimism of his Pelagianism, and
the sincerity of his efforts to promote political reform. If this tension is irreconcilable, it still suggests
Rousseau is a dialectician rather than an abject pessimist. See: Shklar,
Men and Citizens
. For a more
balanced assessment of Rousseau’s sense of futility as an idea later adopted by nineteenth-century
conservatives, see: Starobinski, p. 100.
163
Emile
. E 474.
164
Barber, “How Swiss is Rousseau?” p. 477
61
of Poland, of society—are always moderated by blunt honesty. The Church demands
abject deference. Philosophy cultivates egregious hubris. Rousseau’s worldview, by
contrast, combines both critical realism and active idealism; he worked within the
boundaries of the actual in outlining the horizons of the possible. This is why Poland
may yet democratize, even though the nation fulfilled so few of the essential tenets
outlined in
The Social Contract
. This is why theater—so deadly a threat to virtuous
Geneva—must be accepted in cosmopolitan Paris, a city already given to sin. As for
society, he writes to Voltaire, “a time comes when the evil is such that the very causes
that gave birth to it are necessary to prevent it from becoming larger. It is the sword
that must be left in the wound for fear that the wounded person will die when it is
removed.”
165
In dreaming of a better future, Rousseau is always nagged by this
sword in his side.
This is not simply dramatic overstatement; virtuous reform
necessarily
begins
with such an honest awareness of man
as he is
. As described in the preface to the
Second Discourse
, “[t]he most useful and least advanced of all human knowledge
seems to me to be that of man; and I dare say that the inscription of the Temple of
Delphi alone contained a Precept more important and more difficult than all the thick
Volumes of the Moralists.”
166
Know thyself! Political philosophers must invoke the
Oracle’s inscription.
167
As with Socrates, wise or useful speculation proceeds only
from self-knowledge.
168
It is from this understanding of the “very Nature of man,…
165
Réponse à Voltaire
, September 10, 1755. CW III.106; OC 227.
166
Preface to the Second Discourse
. CW III.12; OC III.122.
167
Readers should consult Socrates’ description of the Delphic injunction in
Apology
20D-22E. See:
Plato,
The Last Days of Socrates
, pp. 49-51.
168
By contrast, Tracy Strong argues that for Rousseau it is “precisely ‘becoming someone else’ that
enables him to know himself.” “The purpose of knowing himself is not in the end
self
-knowledge,”
but a means of painting “a portrait of himself as he is, as a human being… [that] will then be available
62
his constitution and his state, that the principles of that science [of natural right] must
be deduced.”
169
Likewise, as Rousseau later asserts in the
Social Contract
, only by
understanding “men as they are” might we deduce “laws as they can be.”
170
No mean feat, studying man involves a good deal of conjecture. Philosophers
possess a meager understanding of nature, and “one notes the little agreement which
prevails on this important matter among the various Authors who have discussed
it.”
171
Yet neither this lack of consensus, nor the difficulty of the enterprise, deterred
Rousseau. As he wrote in the
Preface to the Second Discourse
,
The same study of original man, of his true needs, and of the
fundamental principles of his duties, is also the only good means one
could use to remove those crowds of difficulties which present
themselves concerning the origin of moral inequality, the true
foundations of the Body politic, the reciprocal rights of its members,
and a thousand similar questions as important as they are ill
explained.
172
Genealogy, we are reminded, is an essentially negative enterprise. It looks backwards
and reveals problems, as in Nietzsche’s exposé of Judeo-Christian morality and
Foucault’s histories of punishment and sexuality.
173
For Rousseau, genealogy is also
to others.” Strong uses this argument to debunk the possible conclusion that Rousseau is engaging in a
precursory form of identity politics. Perhaps. But as I argue here, self-knowledge is a necessary
starting point for species-knowledge, without which prescriptive politics are untenable. Rousseau’s
image of himself certainly provides a pedagogical model for others. Yet structurally, in the
Second
Discourse
for example, self-knowledge precedes the transformation of society (the phenomenon
Strong labels “becoming someone else”). Simply put, to envision reform, we must first understand the
subject of reform. For Rousseau, this clarity begins with following the Delphic injunction. See: Tracy
B. Strong,
Jean-Jacques Rousseau: The Politics of the Ordinary
,
New Edition
. (Lanham, MD:
Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 2002), p. 17.
169
Preface to the Second Discourse
. CW III.13; OC.III.124.
170
The Social Contract
. CW IV.131; OC III.351.
171
Preface to the Second Discourse
. CW III.13; OC III.124.
172
Preface to the Second Discourse
. CW III.15; OC III.126.
173
See: Friedrich Nietzsche,
On the Genealogy of Morals and Ecce Homo
, Walter Kaufmann and R.J.
Hollingdale, tr. (New York: Random House, 1967); Michel Foucault,
Discipline & Punish: The Birth
of the Prison
, Alan Sheridan, tr. (New York: Random House, 1979); Foucault,
The History of
Sexuality, Volume I: An Introduction
, Robert Hurley, tr. (New York: Random House, 1978).
63
practical and prescriptive.
174
Exploring our origins and development allows us to
contrast our unfettered selves in nature with our denatured political identities. In turn,
we can define and distinguish between natural and political rights, natural freedoms
and political obligation. Virtuous political reform demands understanding our present
woes, which logically follows the study of our physical, social and moral
evolution.
175
There is an additional motive at play in Rousseau’s use of speculative history,
one that returns us to the problem of paradox. In his narrative of the fall, he
challenged the Christian ontology of Original Sin as a false opinion. To pacify an
audience which accepted Adam’s legacy as gospel truth, Rousseau qualified his
counter-narrative as conjecture. As he described,
Religion commands us to believe that since God Himself took Men out
of the state of Nature immediately after creation, they are unequal
because He wanted them to be so; but it does not forbid us to form
conjectures, drawn solely from the nature of man and the Beings
surrounding him, about what the human Race might have become if it
had remained abandoned to itself.
176
Rousseau here understood “religion” as Christianity. Scripture taught us that God
banished man from Eden. Our fall was our fault, the result of a sinfully curious (and
174
Interestingly, Robert Nozick—whose worldview is fairly categorized as antithetical to Rousseau’s
own—makes a similar claim. As Nozick argues, “State-of-nature explanations of the political realm
are fundamental potential explanations of this realm, and pack explanatory punch and illumination,
even if incorrect.” Additionally, “We learn much by seeing how the state could have arisen, even if it
didn’t arise that way. If it didn’t arise that way, we would also learn much by determining why it
didn’t; by trying to explain why the particular bit of the real world that diverges from the state-of-
nature model is as it is.” As with Rousseau, Nozick’s endeavor is not, by his own description,
necessarily accurate. A state-of-nature argument may not explain every event in the real world.
Actual events may well deviate from this theoretical model. But even if nature and state, theory and
event, follow divergent paths, investigating this schism is itself revealing, and necessary in defining the
state’s legitimacy. See Nozick,
Anarchy, State, and Utopia
. (New York: Basic Books, Inc., 1974), pp.
4, 6, 8-9.
175
As Rousseau writes in
The Confessions
, “[t]o establish the duties of man one must go back to their
principle.” CW V.77; OC I.91.
176
Second Discourse
. CW III.19; OC III.133.
64
curiously sinful) nature, and the imperfection of our less-than-divine, errant free will.
Yet because God crafted us, this fateful descent conformed to His divine design.
Papal logic therefore placed Original Sin above reproach; challenging the notion was
tantamount to attacking the will of the “Author of all things.” Undeterred, Rousseau
identified a loophole. This doctrine of Original Sin came from Scripture
as
interpreted by man
. As another mere mortal, was he not also free to speculate? Was
this not the very enterprise undertaken by the Church itself in cultivating such myths?
And if freed from the punitive fable of a vengeful God, he wondered, what might we
look like? How might we shape our future, and wherein lies the key to our
redemption?
For starters, we must redress the guilt of crimes imputed to us by the Christian
narrative. It is precisely on this point of intrinsic goodness that papists
and
philosophers have erred. Hobbes, for example, incorrectly concluded that “because
man has no idea of goodness [in the state of nature] he is naturally evil; that he is
vicious because he does not know virtue.”
177
In typically paradoxical fashion,
Rousseau argued precisely the contrary, outlining his first concise doctrine of natural
goodness. This goodness is defined by its innocence, sheltered in a natural state from
the pernicious effects of society and social interactions. In this pre-moral, pre-human
state, envy, hubris, and the most destructive human passions have yet to be born. We
feel only simple
amour-de-soi
and
pitié
.
Pitié
, a “natural feeling,” fulfills several functions: it
contributes to the mutual preservation of the entire species. It carries
us to the aid of those whom we see suffer; in the state of Nature, it
177
This is a slightly misleading description of Hobbes, for whom man in nature was morally neutral
and aggressively self-interested.
Second Discourse
. CW III.35; OC III.153.
65
takes the place of Laws, morals, and virtue, with the advantage that no
one is tempted to disobey its gentle voice; it will deter every robust
Savage from robbing a weak child or an infirm old man of his hard-
won subsistence if he himself hopes to be able to find his own
elsewhere.
178
The Hobbesian state of nature portrayed a war of all-against-all waged by calculating,
rationally self-interested individuals.
179
For Rousseau, Hobbes’ confusion was
conceptual. He imputed denatured developmental faculties (reason, avarice) to
natural creatures. Our natural state was plagued by none of these vices. More
precisely, vice (
and
virtue) followed societal development, particularly civic
interactions, mores, and laws. Rousseau’s depiction of the natural state was by
contrast a benign condition of individuals characterized by instinctual self-
preservation (
amour-de-soi
), and bound by an innate recognition of interdependence,
the intuition that survival is somehow linked to that of one’s fellow creatures (
pitié
).
Rousseau gleaned a golden rule from these concepts, one that supplanted “that
sublime maxim of reasoned justice,
Do unto others as you would have them do unto
you
” with “this other maxim of natural goodness, much less perfect but perhaps more
useful than the preceding one:
Do what is good for you with the least possible harm to
others
.”
180
We possess natural sentiments of both self-preservation and
connectedness to our species. This combination of
amour-de-soi
and
pitié
provides a
178
Second Discourse
. CW.III.37; OC.III.156.
179
From
De Cive
, Chapter I, “In men’s mutual fear,” §12: “…it cannot be denied that men’s natural
state, before they came together into society, was War; and not simply war, but a war of every man
against every man.” Thomas Hobbes,
On the Citizen
, Richard Tuck and Michael Silverthorne, trs.
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), p. 29. From
Leviathan
, Part I, Chapter 13: “Hereby
it is manifest, that during the time men live without a common Power to keep them all in awe, they are
in that condition which is called Warre; and such a warre, as if of every man, against every man.”
Hobbes,
Leviathan
,
Revised Edition
, Richard Tuck, ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1996), p. 88.
180
Second Discourse
. CW III.37-38; OC III.156.
66
pre-moral code which, unlike juridical law, we instinctively obey to mutually
beneficial results.
“In a word,” Rousseau argued, “it is this Natural feeling, rather than in subtle
arguments, that we must seek the cause of the repugnance every man would feel in
doing evil.”
181
The evidence of our capacity to cohabitate lies inscribed in our very
natures. Where a justification based upon “subtle argumentation” requires reason and
reflection, Rousseau’s proofs were unmediated by the intellect. His argument speaks
directly to our hearts,
and
may be confirmed by the mind. It intuitively makes
sense
.
And it assumes, of course, that humankind is not sinful by nature.
Long before the
Savoyard Vicar
, then, Rousseau was preaching a form of
Pelagianism.
182
His vision of reform—of creating more virtuous bonds in an
unnatural world, thereby reinstituting our natural freedom—presupposed this positive
foundation of natural goodness. Freed from Adam’s legacy, we might drastically
improve our fates; an innocent nature suggested nothing less. This assertion that
untainted by society, we would seek what is best for ourselves
and
those around us,
therefore preceded the more explicit denial of Original Sin found in
Emile
. But the
essential charge remained: the problem of vice is social, and therefore of man’s
making, not ontological, or of God’s making. Adam’s legacy was swiftly debunked,
replaced by an
unnecessarily
self-incurred fall.
Vice came from without, from the advent of social relations in denatured
societies. How, then, did society emerge?
183
Humankind, increasing in numbers,
aligned in herds, free associations held together by passing needs, limited obligations,
181
Second Discourse
. CW III.38; OC III.156.
182
For a further discussion of this connection see Chapter 3 below.
183
For Rousseau’s full account see:
Second Discourse
, CW III.43-55; OC III.164-179.
67
and immediate interests. From this occurred the “first revolution”: the familial unit,
where language and conjugal love develop. Families over time evolved into tribes,
which in turn gave rise to social distinctions and morality, virtue and vice. The
turning point occurred when “[t]he first person who, having fenced off a plot of
ground, took it into his head to say
this is mine
and found people simple enough to
believe him.”
184
This concept of private property, the true foundation of civil society
and an idea born slowly over time, led us to “forget that the fruits belong to all and
the Earth to no one.”
185
It also transformed natural inequalities into social
inequalities. The stronger and the smarter, for example, used these natural benefits to
acquire property, and establish and secure social institutions that privileged the fruits
of their labors. The dangerous pride of possessive self-interest subsequently took
root, and the rest, as they say, is history—woeful, at that.
Rousseau’s narrative was received by many as the pessimistic polemic of a
deranged luddite. Prodded by his paradoxes, people not only vilified the Genevan;
they also misread him. He was most commonly charged with promoting a retarding
socialism, with seeking to send us back to egalitarian nature, tails between our legs.
As Voltaire put it, “[o]ne acquires the desire to walk on all fours when one reads your
work.”
186
But Rousseau’s ideas were far more threatening. In an age of progress and
perfectionism, he dared to propose that human development had ambivalent
consequences. To Christian nations, he had the temerity to reject Original Sin. And
against the upper classes, he attacked property generally and vested interests
specifically. His pessimism and optimism alike were affronts to the age.
184
Second Discourse
. CW III.43; OC III.164.
185
Second Discourse
. CW III.43; OC III.164.
186
Letter from Voltaire to Rousseau
(August 30, 1755). CW III.102; CC III.317.157.
68
Rousseau made plain that humankind neither should nor can (by definition)
return to a pre-human existence. We might and
must
, however, redirect the miserable
course of our history. We must redouble our efforts not on an impossible return, but
on social solutions which redeem and protect natural freedom and goodness, while
correcting the damage wrought of artificial inequalities.
* * * * *
If history offers any indication, the odds of success seem unlikely. After all,
our fall was steady and precipitous; reversing this trend requires nothing less than
social reformation. On these points, the
Second Discourse
is unequivocal.
Redressing our self-incurred wrongs calls for a radical reeducation, a pedagogy which
both inures us to and recasts the social relationships which subject our freedom to the
tyrannies of inequality and opinion.
It is thus that Rousseau’s educational treatise necessarily employs paradox.
Not only does he challenge the educational paradigms of his age, he questions the
very mechanisms of society, the very essence of contemporary opinion. Chained by
adverse attachments and desires, individuals might reclaim their natural goodness
only by first resisting the coercive pull of social relations. To reverse our fall we
must strike at the heart of our misery, challenging opinions such as Original Sin
(which leave us hopelessly at God’s post-mortem mercy), but also the opinions of our
fellow creatures (which cultivate perverse passions and destructive desires).
69
If
The Social Contract
envisioned a good society to promote natural goodness,
Emile
wondered how individuals may preserve their goodness in a bad society. We
quickly learn that the well-educated individual—one raised in accord with nature—
must be sheltered from harmful influence. As Rousseau advised in Book II of
Emile
,
“the first education ought to be purely negative. It consists not at all in teaching
virtue or truth but in securing the heart from vice and the mind from error.”
187
Education is negative in the defensive sense: it guards individuals against external
corruption. Such resistance is possible only if we allow children to develop their
natural instinct and judgment. “Reason alone teaches us to know good and bad,”
Rousseau writes. “Conscience, which makes us love the former and hate the latter,
although independent of reason, cannot therefore be developed without it.”
188
Conscience (emotion and will), not reason (mind and intellect) provides humankind
with a natural moral compass.
189
As the Vicar reminds, “I have only to consult
myself about what I want to do. Everything I sense to be good is good; everything I
sense to be bad is bad.”
190
Conscience, that “innate principle of justice and virtue
according to which, in spite of our own maxims, we judge our actions and those of
others as good or bad,”
191
is nonetheless
timid; it likes refuge and peace. The world and noise scare it; the
prejudices from which they claim it is born are its cruelest enemies. It
flees or keeps quiet before them. Their noisy voices stifle its voice and
prevent it from making itself heard. Fanaticism dares to counterfeit it
and to dictate crime in its name. It finally gives up as a result of being
dismissed.”
192
187
Emile
. E 93.
188
Emile
. E 67.
189
In this, Rousseau follows a classically voluntarist trope which identifies the will (and not the
intellect) as humankind’s most Divine faculty.
190
Emile
. E 286.
191
Emile
. E 289.
192
Emile
. E 291.
70
If Rousseau presupposed human goodness, he also assumed society’s perverseness.
Conscience, a timid woodland creature, must therefore be nurtured in nature away
from the prejudices of the cruel, noisy world.
Given this corrupting dynamic of social interactions, people require
compelling force to follow their natural instincts. Until they are capable of clear
reasoning and sound judgment, pupils must be unknowing subjects discouraged from
acquiring social attachments. In Rousseau’s ominous words, “Let him always believe
he is the master, and let it always be you who are. There is no subjection so perfect
as that which keeps the appearance of freedom. Thus the will itself is made
captive.”
193
Emile’s positive moral lessons are also drawn in negative terms: “The only
lesson of morality appropriate to childhood, and the most important for every age, is
never to harm anyone.”
194
We have already seen this “golden rule” introduced in the
Second Discourse
. In addition, it draws upon a discussion of justice in the
Republic
in which Socrates concludes that “it has become apparent to us that it is never just to
harm anyone.”
195
Rousseau also follows Luther, who argued that good works (which
we can control, unlike motives or good faith) are no measure of a grace free of
193
Emile
. E 120. Sentences such as these do not help Rousseau’s reputation as a totalitarian thinker.
The tutor-pupil role clearly evokes Antonio Gramsci’s definition of hegemony as a coercive system
strengthened by its insidiousness. In Rousseau’s defense, the control of a young pupil’s will is
necessary for two reasons: first, youth are not yet developmentally capable of sound judgment and self-
rule; and second, his extreme stance is dictated by an extreme situation. Raising people according to
nature while shielding them from society demands holding their uncorrupted wills in captivity. The
Tutor must “force” Emile to be free in order to manipulate his pupil to follow his natural conscience.
Readers should compare this to
The Social Contract
, I.VII: “whoever refuses to obey the general will
shall be constrained to do so by the entire body; which means only that he will be forced to be free.”
CW IV.141; OC III.364.
194
Emile
. E 104.
195
The Republic
I.335e (Bloom 13).
71
contrivance.
196
Good works do not offer a normative moral standard, for “[w]ho does
not do good? Everybody does it—the wicked man as well as others. He makes one
man happy at the expense of making a hundred men miserable; and this is the source
of all our calamities.”
197
What is good for one is not necessarily good for many.
Recalling Rousseau’s study of inequality, this simple reminder reinforces the
dangers of particular self-interest, even when acted upon under the auspices of public
good. The architects of Lisbon, for example, may well have believed that they were
serving society’s best interests in building the eighteenth-century equivalent of sky-
scrapers. But the earthquake of 1755, and the subsequent damage precipitated by the
destruction of such unnatural constructions, multiplied our misery.
198
As such,
Rousseau concludes that caution is sometimes in order. “The most sublime virtues
are negative” because restraint reduces the likelihood that we will harm our
fellows.
199
Finally, even the Savoyard Vicar begins his sermon with a negative lesson. In
matters of speculation he learns “to limit my researches to what was immediately
related to my interest, to leave myself in a profound ignorance of all the rest, and to
worry myself to the point of doubt only about things it was important for me to
196
For Luther, a good heart (not good works) reveals the depth of human faith. If anything, good
works are misleading, allowing those of impure motives an easy way of serving God. Clearly for
Luther, “ease” had no role in true piousness. As he writes in
Preface to the Epistle of Saint Paul to the
Romans
: “God judges according to your inmost convictions; His law must be fulfilled in your very
heart, and cannot be obeyed if you merely perform certain acts.” And in
The Freedom of a Christian
:
“Let this suffice concerning the inner man, his liberty, and the source of his liberty, the righteousness
of faith. He needs neither laws nor good works but, on the contrary, is injured by them if he believes
that he is justified by them.” From:
Martin Luther: Selections from His Writings
, pp. 20, 66-67.
197
Emile
. E 105.
198
Readers should consult Pope’s
Essay on Man
and Voltaire’s
Poème sur le désastre de Lisbonne
.
199
Emile
. E 105.
72
know.”
200
Against the vain grasp of philosophers generally and the dysfunctional
doubt of skeptics specifically, he preaches the practical value of self-imposed limits.
Following these examples, Emile’s tutelage may be described as negative in at
least four respects. First, it reflects a critical assessment of contemporary education.
Second, it understands virtue as a passive value (doing “no harm” rather than doing
“some good”). Third, it describes development as a process of sheltering and
resistance. And fourth, it guards against the cultivation of unnatural desires, urges
defined by the weakness of unnecessary want or perceived lack.
In brief, Emile’s education finds fortitude through resistance. As late as Book
IV Jean-Jacques notes with some satisfaction that “[o]pinion, whose actions [Emile]
sees, has not acquired its empire over him.”
201
Soon after, he writes that “[i]t suffices
that, enclosed in a social whirlpool, [Emile] not let himself get carried away by either
the passions or the opinions of men.”
202
And finally, we are asked “who in the world
is less of an imitator than Emile? Who is less governed by ridicule than the man who
has no prejudices and does not know how to concede anything to those of others?”
203
In other words, who is more immune to the empire of opinion than the Tutor’s prized
pupil?
Rousseau’s education inures Emile to the opinions of others, and for as long
as possible. But why? Prior to Vicar’s
Profession of Faith
, he justifies this practice
in terms reminiscent of the
Second Discourse’s
fall. Amidst a discussion on love,
200
Emile
. E 269. Rousseau reiterates this claim (in his “own” voice) in the
Reveries
. Describing how
he overcame the doubts instilled in him by his
philosophe
peers which left him “not wiser, more
learned, or of better faith than when I settled all those great questions,” he concludes that “I therefore
limited myself to what was within my reach, without getting myself involved in what went beyond it.”
See:
Reveries
(Third Promenade). CW VIII.25; OC I.1021-1022.
201
Emile
. E 244.
202
Emile
. E 255.
203
Emile
. E 331.
73
Rousseau describes the evolution of human attachment. We begin with hearts
naturally overflowing with love, yet lacking companionship. In a desire to secure
reciprocal adoration, we acquire a mistress. This new intimacy in turn creates a
correlative need for friendship. From this apparently harmless (and undoubtedly
natural) pull, we suddenly fall prey to the opinions of others. “With love and
friendship are born dissensions, enmity, and hate. From the bosom of so many
diverse passions I see opinion raising an unshakable throne, and stupid mortals,
subjected to its empire, basing their own existence on the judgment of others.”
204
The turn of events is somewhat shocking. We start, innocently enough, with
pure hearts and motives, and end under the rule of
doxa’s
“unshakable throne,”
trapped by the attachments to which we were naturally drawn. Here, then, is the
evolution of
amour-de-soi
to
amour-propre
described in social terms, with no less
disastrous consequences. To preserve Emile’s freedom and natural goodness, the
Tutor must occlude his reliance upon others. The impressionable youth must rely
upon the singular judgment of his ward until he is capable of self-legislation. He
must be sheltered from society until he is strong enough to resist its pull.
The pupil must also avoid exposure to that which his mind cannot yet
comprehend. This is why the Tutor withholds religion. “I foresee how many readers
will be surprised at seeing me trace the whole first age of my pupil without speaking
to him of religion,” Rousseau writes. “At fifteen he did not know whether he had a
soul. And perhaps at eighteen it is not yet time to learn it; for if he learns it sooner
than he ought, he runs the risk of never knowing it.”
205
The argument is logistical,
204
Emile
. E 215.
205
Emile
. E 257.
74
not theological. Children are not developmentally capable of understanding religion,
any more than they are capable of fine reasoning or self-rule. Rousseau therefore
does “not see what is gained by teaching [catechisms] to children, unless it be that
they learn how to lie early.”
206
The mysteries of God and divinity are lost on youth
for whom, “[a]t the age when everything is mystery, there are no mysteries strictly
speaking.”
207
If “[t]he obligation to believe assumes the possibility of doing so,”
children are simply not able.
208
Where the
Second Discourse
painted in broad, sweeping strokes,
Emile
is
much more specific. The Church requires children to learn lessons contrary to
nature.
209
It inundates pupils with ideas which they cannot yet comprehend. This
emphasis on rote repetition reflects a more significant problem: by privileging their
own hollow platitudes, the Church fails to cultivate genuine faith. If “[i]t is especially
in matters of religion that opinion triumphs,” there is no greater culprit than a Church
whose righteous opinions take the dangerous form of aggressively intolerant
gospel.
210
By Rousseau’s description, papists also ground their authority on a tautology:
“The Church decides that the Church has the right to decide.”
211
The certainty of
their judgment is matched only by the circularity of their logic. More dangerously,
the dogmatism of this conviction breeds despotic conformity. Presaging Rousseau’s
own censure, the Vicar asks “what is there to do? If someone dared to publish among
206
Emile
. E 257.
207
Emile
. E 257.
208
Emile
. E 257.
209
Given Rousseau’s description of nature as a product (and reflection) of the divine will, this also
represented an offense against God.
210
Emile
. E 260.
211
Emile
. E 304.
75
us books in which Judaism were openly favored, we would punish the author, the
publisher, the bookseller. This is a convenient and sure policy for always being right.
There is a pleasure in refuting people who do not dare to speak.”
212
Rousseau was no deliberative democrat, as the
Social Contract
makes clear.
213
But neither was he a totalitarian.
214
The general will is by definition the will shared
by all in common, not the will imposed upon us from above. By contrast, the Church
would have us believe that they alone possess true faith, and criminalize opposing
visions. But if we simply look around us, piety is evident in all peoples. “Cast your
eyes on all the nations of the world, go through all the histories,” the Vicar urges.
“Among so many inhuman and bizarre cults, among this prodigious diversity of
morals and characters, you will find everywhere the same ideas of justice and
decency, everywhere the same notions of good and bad.”
215
Even in Pagan cultures
has “[t]he holy voice of nature, stronger than that of the gods, made itself respected
212
Emile
. E 303-304. In an author’s note, Rousseau earlier takes the Stoics to task for similarly
discounting the value of discussion: “Plutarch reports that the Stoics maintained, among other bizarre
paradoxes, that in an adversary proceeding it was useless to hear the two parties.” (E 302n) The
reference is to Plutarch’s essay “On Stoic Self-Contradictions,” 1034E: “Against him who said / Nor
give your verdict till you’ve heard both sides / Zeno asserted the contrary with an argument something
like this: The second speaker must not be heard whether the former speaker proved his case (for then
the inquiry is at an end) or did not prove it (for that is tantamount to his not having appeared when
summoned or to having responded to the summons with mere gibberish); but either he proved his case
or he did not prove it; therefore, the second speaker must not be heard. After he had propounded this
argument, however, he continued to write against Plato’s Republic, to refute sophisms, and to bid his
pupils to learn dialectic on the ground that it enables one to do this. Yet either Plato proved or did not
prove what is in the Republic, and either way it was not necessary but was utterly superfluous and vain
to write against it. The same thing can be said about sophisms also.” See: Plutarch,
Moralia: Volume
XIII, Part II
, Harold Cherniss, tr. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1976), pp. 427 & 429.
213
See:
The Social Contract
Book II, Chapter 3, “Whether the General Will Can Err.”
214
For “totalitarian” critiques of Rousseau see: Talmon,
The Origins of Totalitarian Democracy
;
Crocker,
Rousseau’s Social Contract
; Berlin,
Four Essays on Liberty
; Huizinga,
The Self Made Saint
.
Arthur M. Melzer also argues that Rousseau promotes an “antiliberal” democracy “not to establish, but
to eliminate men’s rights against the state. All private, natural rights are to be totally alienated in
exchange for political rights, for a share in control over the absolute and unlimited state.” At the very
least, this reading misappropriates Rousseau’s strict division between general (public) and particular
(private) rights, and obscures his definition of the general will as the will that each individual shares in
common. See:
The Natural Goodness of Man
, p. 109.
215
Emile
. E 288.
76
on earth and seemed to regulate crime, along with the guilty, to heaven.”
216
Well
before the Church, reverence of nature—much like
pitié
and more than polytheism—
served a normative social function in the form of a regulative moral code. Its
authority was rooted not in the sophistication of human reasoning, but in a simple
appreciation of the natural world order. It is in such divine—not human—creations
that we may find evidence of the “Author of all things,” and glean necessary
inspiration from His perfection.
By forcing us to comply to their mediated vision, Christians ironically debase
faith and breed intolerance. Speaking on salvation, the Vicar explains: “
You must
believe in God to be saved
. This dogma badly understood is the principle of
sanguinary intolerance and the cause of all those vain instructions that strike a fatal
blow to human reason in accustoming it to satisfy itself with words.”
217
But
salvation, like true piety, is more than a matter of rote repetition: “if in order to obtain
it, it is enough to repeat certain words, I do not see what prevents us from peopling
heaven with starlings and magpies just as well as with children.”
218
If the Church parades dogma as spirituality, reduces worship to compulsory
recitation, and peddles it to unawares, what is Rousseau’s alternative vision of true
religion? What is genuine faith? It appears as a form of both rational appreciation
and an awareness of the limitations of human reason: appreciating God’s creation,
and accepting the incomprehensible wisdom of his order. As the Vicar expounds,
216
Emile
. E 288-289.
217
Emile
. E 257.
218
Emile
. E 257. For a similar argument, readers should also consult Montaigne’s
Of Pedantry
in
The
Complete Essays of Montaigne
, Donald M. Frame, tr. (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1958), pp.
97-106.
77
The greatest ideas of the divinity come to us from reason alone. View
the spectacle of nature; hear the inner voice. Has God not told
everything to our eyes, to our conscience, to our judgment? What
more will men tell us? Their revelations have only the effect of
degrading God by giving Him human passions. I see that particular
dogmas, far from clarifying the notions of the great Being, confuse
them; that far from ennobling them, they debase them; that to the
inconceivable mysteries surrounding the great Being they add absurd
contradictions; that they make man proud, intolerant, and cruel; that,
instead of establishing peace on earth, they bring sword and fire to it. I
ask myself what good all this does, without knowing what to answer. I
see in it only the crimes of men and the miseries of mankind.
219
Teaching by negation, we learn that religion is
not
a particularly misguided vision of
God. It is not the imposition of human passions upon a Being surely devoid of these
qualities. If the Author of all things is characterized by immaculate order,
contradictions and confusions do not describe him. If he is a wise, benevolent deity
who loves his creations, his worship should not facilitate cruel intolerance. To
understand religion we must first reject the dogmas preached by an historically
violent church and look to nature, whose wonder and coherent order is a clearer
testament of God’s grace than any catechism.
Although spoken by the Vicar, the charge reveals themes consistent with
Rousseau’s own beliefs. Foremost amongst them is his abhorrence of mediation.
220
Papists have attributed vengeance and justified bloodshed to the service of a surely
munificent God. And in so doing, they have committed an act of vile
transubstantiation, imputing their own malicious, particular interests to the One they
purportedly serve. As Rousseau later writes in the first of his
Letters Written From
the Mountain
, his enemies “put themselves in the place of God to do the work of the
219
Emile
. E 295.
220
In
Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Transparency and Obstruction
, Starobinski persuasively identifies this
love of immediacy and detestation of mediation as the unifying theme of Rousseau’s
oeuvres
.
78
Devil.”
221
Entranced by “that dangerous
amour-propre
which always wants to carry
men above his sphere,” they have lowered God to ours while placing themselves in-
between.
222
The empire of their opinion knows no bounds. The papacy has extended their
rule to the heavens. They would have us accept their interpretation as gospel, and
God as their puppet. “As soon as peoples took it into their heads to make God speak,
each made Him speak in its own way and made Him say what it wanted,” the Vicar
laments.
223
Yet “[i]f one had listened only to what God says to the heart of man,
there would never have been more than one religion on earth.”
224
This argument for religious tolerance is grounded in a classically voluntarist
belief in the impenetrable mysteries of divinity. Neither Rousseau, nor the Vicar, nor
M. de Beaumont can tell us who God really is, what He looks like, or when He speaks
only to us.
225
And unlike mythic Pagan history, such interpretations have served
decidedly unvirtuous ends. Instead of solidifying universal brotherhood, the Church
has used dogma and Scripture to create divisions, to bring blood and fire upon the
earth of God’s creation. Instead of affirming the truth that God created us all, they
221
Letters Written From the Mountain
(First Letter). OC III.697; CW.IX.141.
222
Emile
. E 296.
223
Emile
. E 295.
224
Emile
. E 295.
225
Although voiced by the Vicar, this mirrors Rousseau’s own condemnation of miracles as vain
presumptions that God would take the time to speak directly to select individuals. In this position,
Rousseau follows Malebranche, who argued that God was defined by simplicity and consistency in His
perfection, not intrusion into the particular affairs of humankind. In
Elucidations of the Search After
Truth
, Malebranche says that sinners “would have God perform miracles in their favor and not follow
the ordinary laws of grace.” More directly, in the Fourth of his
Dialogues on Metaphysics
, he states
that “God never performs miracles. He never acts by special volitions contrary to His own laws which
Order does not require or permit. His conduct always manifests the character of His attributes.”
Miracles clearly “do not follow His general laws.” (Eighth Dialogue) From:
Nicolas Malebranche:
Philosophical Selections
, Steven Nadler, ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1992),
pp. 109, 188-189, 242. For a convincing, clear and thorough discussion of this connection see: Riley,
The General Will Before Rousseau
.
79
cultivate violent artificial boundaries. Yet rather than accept such deadly
interpretations as God’s word, we can (and should) intuitively
feel
His existence, and
recognize our common bond as His creations. This heartfelt sentiment is confirmed
by observation: by appreciating the world of his making, by finding examples of
pious love and fraternity in peoples of all nations.
Following in the Protestant tradition, the Vicar reminds us to
not confuse the ceremony of religion with religion itself. The worship
God asks for is that of the heart. And that worship, when it is sincere,
is always uniform. One must be possessed of a mad vanity indeed to
imagine that God takes so great an interest in the form of the priest’s
costume, in the order of the words he pronounces, in the gestures he
makes at the altar, and in all his genuflections.
226
Worship is a matter of individual conscience, not conformity to sectarian ceremony.
If God truly presides over this and all other worlds, his adulation should be equally
unconstrained. This, after all, “is the duty of all religions, all countries, all men” who
serve a (or more precisely
the
) single deity.
227
Beyond that, particular forms of worship are somewhat arbitrary.
228
“The
226
Emile
. E 296.
227
Emile
. E 296
228
Paolo Toscanelli (1397-1482), an accomplished mathematician and scholar, believed that ships
could sail to Asia far more quickly than had previously been imagined by altering traditional westward
routes. He presented a chart of his findings to the Court of Portugal. Although King John II was wary,
Christopher Columbus—then a mapmaker and entrepreneur—was intrigued. This conclusion
reaffirmed the work of classical geographer Marinus of Tyre, the travelogues of Venetian merchant
Marco Polo, and Columbus’ own study of the Apocrypha (particularly II Esdras 6:42) that argued the
earth was almost entirely (six-sevenths) composed of land. Armed with Toscanelli’s support,
Columbus eventually convinced the Spanish monarchy (under Ferdinand) to fund an Oriental
expedition. This voyage, of course, led him
eastwards
, where he “discovered” a New World inhabited
by “savages”—peoples untouched by Christianity.
Columbus’ accidental discovery led many others to follow his mistaken path to the Americas.
One of these explorers was his friend Amerigo Vespucci who, beginning in 1502, made several
voyages to the New World. It was during this period that Vespucci’s cousin Agostino served as both
confidant and assistant to Niccolo Machiavelli (assisting, for example, on an ambitious engineering
project of Machiavelli’s between 1503 and 1506). Machiavelli, famously denounced by Jesuits,
Humanists, Roman Catholics, counter-Reformationists, Huguenots, and French Monarchists (amongst
others) was seen as an intellectual threat to the political and philosophical dominance of Christian
theology in the pre-Enlightenment world.
80
faith of children and of many men is a question of geography.”
229
Choice of religion
is likewise “the effect of chance; to blame [non-Catholics] for it is iniquitous. It is to
reward or punish them for being born in this or in that country. To dare to say that
God judges us in this way is to insult His justice.”
230
Intolerance is anything but
pious. As the Vicar elaborates, “[i]f there were a religion on earth outside of whose
worship there was only eternal suffering, and if in some place in the world a single
mortal of good faith had not been struck by its obviousness, the God of that religion
would be the most iniquitous and cruel of tyrants.”
231
But He is not. His justice and grace are both indisputable and universal, and
must be confirmed by appealing to conscience and reason, not dogmatism and
Machiavelli’s godlessness was widely assumed, although (like Rousseau) he is more
accurately described as anticlerical. His
Discourses
identify religion as a crucial catalyst to ancient
Rome’s republican virtue: Numa, not Solon, is credited with this accomplishment. Machiavelli’s
blatant hostility towards the church is storied, but his connection to the New World explorers often
goes unnoticed. The two, I believe, are related.
Christianity assumed a privileged role amongst religions because it was said its missionaries
graced the entire world. The exposure of a vast continent of peoples untouched by the hand of a
Christian God severely tested this supposition. Machiavelli, closely privy to such information, was
certainly aware of this demystifying discovery, whose influence may be gleaned in his denouncement
of the Church. The argument Rousseau makes in the
Emile
on the arbitrariness of particular forms of
worship—written especially in rebuttal to the Papal order—similarly assumes that non-Christians may
be pious, even if they are ignorant of the Church raised in His name. In so doing, he draws upon
precisely such discoveries of heathen lands.
Consider this argument posed by the Vicar: “Two-thirds of mankind are neither Jews nor
Mohammedans nor Christians, and how many million men have never heard of Moses, Jesus Christ, or
Mohammed? This is denied; it is maintained that our missionaries go everywhere. That is easily said.
But do they go into the still unknown heart of Africa,… to deepest Tartary,” Japan or Asia? “Do they
go into the immense continents of America, where whole nations still do not know that peoples from
another world have set foot in theirs?” (E 304) The conclusion is glaring: Christianity is
just another
religion
. This argument rests specifically upon the discovery of “the immense continents of America”
(also the subject of Rousseau’s early opera,
La Découverte du Nouveau Monde
), and its non-Christian
communities. Given this evidence, deism is the
only
form of piety capable of reconciling the universal
truth God’s existence with the seeming savagery of a continent untouched by the Church’s mores.
Readers should consult: Machiavelli,
Discourses on Livy
, Julia Conaway Bondanella and
Peter Bondanella, trs. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), I.11, pp. 50-53;
La Découverte du
Nouveau Monde
. OC I.815-841; CW X.12-36. In addition, I am grateful to Roger D. Masters for
bringing this matter to my attention, and taking the time to sketch its significance.
229
Emile
. E 258.
230
Emile
. E 297.
231
Emile
. E 297.
81
revelation. As the Vicar quips, it matters not what the Church commands in questions
of faith: “I need reasons for subjecting my reason.”
232
Demonstrative proofs, not
human mediation, reveal the will of God: “When I believe what he says, it is not
because he says it but because he proves it. Therefore the testimony of men is at
bottom only that of my own reason and adds nothing to the natural means God gave
me for knowing the truth.”
233
The Church therefore deals in the worst form of sophism, a manipulation of
opinion which compromises our highest, most natural relationship. Consider the
following paragraph, written with an indignation worthy of Luther:
Apostle of the truth, what then have you to tell me of which I do not
remain the judge? “God Himself has spoken. Hear His revelation.”
That is something else. God has spoken! That is surely a great
statement. To whom has He spoken? “He has spoken to men.” Why,
then, did I hear nothing about it? “He has directed other men to give
you His word.” I understand: it is men who are going to tell me what
God has said. I should have preferred to have heard God himself. It
would have cost Him nothing more, and I would have been sheltered
from seduction.
234
This is a mock dialogue in both senses of the word. Taking the form of a hypothetical
conversation with a cleric, it ridicules the idea that only a select few may mediate and
dictate our relationship with God. The very suggestion leaves the Vicar incensed.
“What! Always human testimony? Always men who report to me what other men
have reported! So many men between God and me!”
235
So many fallible human
opinions perverting the practice of faith! So many meddlers confounding the natural
purity of conscience!
232
Emile
. E 297.
233
Emile
. E 297.
234
Emile
. E 297.
235
Emile
. E 297.
82
Rousseau was not simply nay-saying. He firmly believed that dogmatism
discouraged the pious adoration of God. In dictating the terms of external worship,
papal intrusion into corporeal affairs carries unjust consequences. Specific religious
customs, accidents of history and geography but also the free interpretations of the
Divinity’s creatures, are a matter settled amongst citizens, not man and God. “As to
the external worship,” the Vicar advises, “if it must be uniform for the sake of good
order, that is purely a question of public policy; no revelation is needed for that.”
236
Religious custom boils down to a political question of “public policy”; its form must
support the “good order” of strong civil society.
237
This is a social prescription, one which presses upon us the necessity for
living in mutual harmony. Papists (like philosophers) sacrifice society’s general
welfare for the sake of their own (particular) interests. Rousseau, by contrast, insists
that all forms of religion must be allowed so long as they encourage virtuous
(general) order. Conversely, sects which divide and conquer must be banned; they
serve neither God nor state. This becomes a problem of practical fruition, one whose
difficulty is compounded by Rousseau’s own claims. We are innocent by nature and
literally guilty by association. Our fall was ushered by our interactions in society,
which corrupt individual virtue. If the empire of opinion (a ripe phenomenon
amongst religious sects) is particularly blameworthy, how might we find a religion
which retains its civic benefits while avoiding its social pitfalls?
Rousseau outlined his solutions in
Emile
and
The Social Contract
, but his
prescriptions were overshadowed by the grating character of his paradoxes. Jean
236
Emile
. E 296.
237
Readers should consult Rousseau’s concept of Civil Religion in
The Social Contract
, IV.8 and the
Geneva Manuscript
, Book III, both of which I discuss elsewhere in detail.
83
Starobinski illuminates the irony of this predicament, noting that “Rousseau made
himself a stranger to man in order to protect against the alienation that makes men
strangers to one another.”
238
His “renunciation of the world’s vanities and…
conversion to ‘another moral world’
239
took Rousseau not toward the Church but
toward the forest and the life of the vagabond.”
240
It would still take Rousseau some
ten years after
Emile’s
publication to return to the woods for good, to reintroduce
himself to botany and write his final works. But his estrangement began long before
his final retreat.
This rift was facilitated by Rousseau’s paradoxical nature. It was also a
consequence of his inimitable style, the force and certainty with which he pursued
truth and exposed ideas. Prior to 1762, Rousseau nonetheless cast blame elsewhere.
It was the opinions of
others
which rightfully deserve the loaded label of paradox. As
he asserted in the Introduction to his
Fragments politiques
,
But since I have learned through experience the damage that
demonstrated propositions can suffer from being called Paradoxes, I
am relieved to remove this resource in advance from those who have
none other to argue against what I am about to prove. I warn them,
therefore, that it is the opinion I attack that should be called a paradox,
as unheard of to this day as it is ridiculous and pernicious; and that by
refuting this soft and effeminate Philosophy whose convenient maxims
have won it so many supporters among us, I only add my voice to the
cry of all nations, and plead the cause of common sense as well as that
of society.
241
This dual cause—of (naturally) good sense and social welfare—inspired his
contrariness. In the matter of religion, piety is essential and true to both society and
238
Starobinski, p. 41
239
Starobinski’s reference is to the following quote: “Une grande révolution qui venoit de se faire en
moi, un autre monde moral qui se devoiloit à mes regards…”
Reveries
(Third Promenade). OC
I.1015; CW VIII.20.
240
Starobinski, pp. 39-40.
241
Political Fragments
1. CW IV.46; OC III.518.
84
human nature. God’s very magnificence—the scope and effect of his will—reminds
us of his existence, and our mutually-supportive duties as His creations. But the faith
of men as dictated by the Catholic Church discourages such reverence.
As Rousseau’s paradoxes grew even more specific they elicited more severe
consequences. Just as he was compelled to write as he felt, so did he feel compelled
to defend himself from mounting attacks. In the self-justifying works following
1762, he turned to readers to rescue him from the judgments levied by his age. Too
many men of power had too many interests vested in the ideas he opposed. This,
finally, is why Rousseau begged “common readers” to pardon him his paradoxes;
they were, supposedly, written on behalf of the people to whom he appealed.
His request of pardon still belies the insistence of his prose. Paradox was
necessary
, Rousseau writes—and therefore not, strictly speaking, a matter of choice.
But common people—of society, and also of God and nature—might still choose.
Pardon him? The choice is ultimately left neither to Church nor state nor academy,
but to fellow men and citizens. Defending the Vicar’s deism in his
Letters Written
From the Mountain
, Rousseau makes the question characteristically blunt:
[T]he doctrine in question is good for the human race and bad for its
oppressors. In what absolute category must it be put? I have faithfully
stated the pros and cons. Compare and choose.
242
Was he right or wrong, decent or vicious, worthy of praise or blame? In the end, was
his belief in man’s innocence, society’s guilt, and divine beneficence of any use to the
human race? Such are the choices laid before us. Our response either redeems
Rousseau’s perplexing paradoxes, or casts them from the realm of virtuous reverie to
one of well-forgotten memory.
242
Letters Written From the Mountain
(First Letter). CW IX.146; OC III.702.
85
86
Chapter 3: A Claim of Innocence
And so it was “not I” that brought this about “but sin which dwelt in me,” sin
resulting from the punishment of a more freely chosen sin, because I was a son of
Adam.
—Augustine,
Confessions
243
True innocence is ashamed of nothing.
—Rousseau,
Emile
244
When Rousseau begged us to pardon his paradoxes,
245
the request was hardly
hollow. The proliferation of contradictory thought—at odds with others and,
according to critics,
246
itself—gives us ample opportunity to do so. The decision is
still ours to make, but before either granting or denying Rousseau his wish we might
revisit his most compelling, controversial (and hence potentially unpardonable)
paradox: namely, innocence.
243
Saint Augustine,
Confessions
, Henry Chadwick, tr. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991),
VII.x.22, p. 149. Augustine’s Biblical reference is to
Romans
7:17, 20.
244
Emile
. E 217.
245
Emile
. E 93; OC IV.323.
246
Most notably J.H. Huizinga who, citing Benjamin Constant, writes that Rousseau “thrashes about
among a thousand contrary ideas as in a dark night lit up by frequent flashes of lightening.”
Rousseau:
The Self-Made Saint
, p. 268. Huizinga also lists amongst Rousseau’s notable critics William Ralph
Inge, a Christian Platonist and dean of London’s St. Paul’s Cathedral. “The influence of this
sentimental rhetorician,” Inge wrote, “has perhaps been more pernicious than that of any other man
who has ever lived.” Inge,
Christian Ethics and Modern Problems
. (New York: The Knickerbocker
Press, 1930), pp. 249-250. French literary critic Jules Lemaître (“thanks to human credulity and
stupidity no man had ever done more harm to mankind than the writer who, it seems, hardly knew
what he was writing”) and François Mauriac, 1952 winner of the Nobel Prize for Literature (“the
modern era is rooted in his lies… It has taken a century and a half for his poison to accomplish its
work”) likewise saw Rousseau’s legacy as catastrophic. See also: Jules Lemaître,
Jean-Jacques
Rousseau
. (New York: The McClure Company, 1907); François Mauriac,
Trois grands hommes devant
Dieu
. (Paris: Editions du capitale, 1930).
87
Throughout his works, Rousseau maintained his innocence in three crucial
senses:
247
as an
individual
whose writings revealed a uniquely good soul bared to the
public; as a
human being
, an ontological claim that contradicted the orthodox
Christian narrative of Original Sin; and as a
defendant
, a refutation of the charges
levied against him following the publications of
Emile
and
The Social Contract
.
Despite his paradoxes, Rousseau claimed his
oeuvres
were characterized by their
consistency.
248
A thread linking his most provocative positions, innocence offers a
means of locating this continuity.
Such common ground is particularly helpful when reconciling Rousseau’s
religious and political beliefs. After all, his spiritual optimism (epitomized by his
rejection of Original Sin) and social pessimism (revealed in his stark critiques of
contemporary society and human history) seem to push readers in opposite directions.
Rousseau framed the fall of humankind in decidedly Edenic terms as a genealogy of
decline from a blissful natural state to one corrupted by illegitimate societal chains.
Yet he based this dour history upon an optimistic heresy, a renunciation of Original
Sin and correlative faith in the intrinsic goodness of man.
This paradoxical stance left him open to charges of hypocrisy. A virulent
social critic who exalted human nature, Rousseau insisted that society had corrupted
otherwise benevolent creatures. Marveling at the wonder of a natural world alienated
by human artifice, he urged us to follow our God-given consciences and embrace our
divinely-created natures. This is a refrain sung throughout Rousseau’s writings, one
247
Together, this triple claim evokes the four major senses of innocence cited by the
Oxford English
Dictionary
: “freedom from sin, guilt, or moral wrong in general” or “moral purity”; “freedom from
specific guilt” or “not being guilty of that with which one is charged”; “freedom from cunning or
artifice” or “guilelessness”; and “harmlessness, innocuousness.”
248
As I later discuss, Rousseau makes this consistency central to his defense of
Emile
.
88
concisely captured in
Emile
’s famous opening line: “Everything is good as it leaves
the hands of the Author of things; everything degenerates in the hands of man.”
249
An individual uniquely attuned to this intrinsic goodness, Rousseau presented himself
as a testament to the possibility of regeneration.
250
Of course, as his autobiographical writings make clear, Jean-Jacques was no
saint. Far from it, his life was characterized by impulsiveness and fluctuation, from
his early abandonment of Geneva, to his rather capricious conversion to Catholicism,
to his sudden epiphany on the road to Vincennes. He was also guilty of what is
generally considered unsavory or immoral behavior: romantic affairs, indecent
exposure, lies and theft. A man of such blatantly self-described faults who frequently
succumbed to his overwhelming passions should hardly claim absolution from guilt.
Yet for Rousseau, innocence was rooted in something deeper than acts: namely the
goodness of our natural will, a faculty often led astray by social interactions.
251
Given his own suspect personal history, such self-exculpation proved
unconvincing to the many who found him abjectly guilty of crimes against the
church, his
patrie
, and his religion, and breaches of friendship, civic duty, and
249
Emile
. E 37.
250
By this, I do not mean to suggest that Rousseau asks us to follow his life as a model. After all, it is
not entirely evident that this is possible. Consider, for example, his emphasis upon his uniqueness (the
prefatory note to
The Confessions
describes the work as “the only portrait of a man, painted exactly
according to nature and in all its truth, that exists and that probably will ever exist”), and discrepancies
between his own autonomous education (self-directed immersion and remarkable erudition) and that of
Emile’s (which, under the guidance of a highly controlling tutor, actively discourages reading). I do
believe that Rousseau reveals himself as a testament to the
possibility
of living more naturally. If he
himself is an anomaly, his life is still exemplary, and therefore serves a heuristic purpose.
251
As Rousseau writes in
Emile
, “let us set down as an incontestable maxim that the first movements
of nature are always right. There is no original perversity in the human heart.” By contrast, “there is
not a single vice to be found in it of which it cannot be said how and whence it entered.” Because the
natural will never errs and all vice is artificially constructed, actions guided by inner sentiment follow
innocent motives. A return to our innocent nature occurs only in society through this act of free will.
Emile
. E 92. For the foundation of this argument see:
Second Discourse
. CW III.36-38; OC III.155-
157.
89
philosophic decorum. Condemned as an author, an individual, and a human being,
his claim of innocence also constituted a self-defense. Pardoning Rousseau this
paradox therefore determines his culpability—where he errs, where his accusers make
legitimate claims, and (most broadly) where his renunciation of guilt informs a
coherent philosophical vision rather than a convenient self-acquittal.
Whatever the verdict, Rousseau’s triple claim of innocence can hardly be
confined to a question of individual reputation. More than a matter of narrow
interest, it underlies his faith in both religion as a virtuous moral guide and
democracy as the self-rule of essentially good creatures. Do his caustic accusations
and personal misdeeds compromise this optimism? More specifically, does his
renunciation of Original Sin stand at irreconcilable odds with his deeply pessimistic
view of human society? Or does Rousseau’s paradoxical insistence unfold as a
compelling catalyst for politico-theological reform?
To investigate these questions, we will begin by addressing Rousseau’s
testament of personal innocence particularly as revealed in his
Confessions
. Next we
will turn to a discussion of Pelagianism as the foundation of his religious thought, a
creed he most clearly develops in the voice of the Savoyard Vicar. We will then
explore his response to the charges raised in the censure of
Emile
, a defense in which
Rousseau reiterates both his individual and ontological innocence. After examining
this concept in its three major guises, we will be poised to judge the coherence and
cohesion of his claim. In so doing, we will determine not only whether we may
pardon him his most illustrious paradox; we may also see how this controversial
90
notion illuminates the dialectic between spiritual perfectionism and secular pessimism
so central to his political philosophy.
* * * * *
To read Rousseau as he requested we must allow him his manifold paradoxes
while struggling to find unity between his many discourses and novels, letters and
plays, treatises and personal reveries. Reading Rousseau therefore demands not
simply a strong constitution; it also requires a good deal of patience. To hold him to
his oft-repeated claims of consistency and honesty, utility and acuity, we must treat
his massive
oeuvre
as an old Genevan watch: dissect it with courage and caution,
while wondering whether the parts still fit a working whole.
Answers are far from self-evident. In different styles and tones Rousseau
revealed sharply different takes on humankind’s past (a descent from natural harmony
to artificial subjugation), present (a disastrous empire of opinion guided by academic
and papal hubris), and possible future (legitimizing the chains of our mutual
attachments through radical democratic reform). The very faculties—free will,
imagination, sociability—that contributed to our decline allowed us the possibility of
redemption. This purported solution was further complicated by Rousseau’s
subversiveness: both his pessimistic realism and optimistic perfectionism were based
upon stark critiques of his own age.
Rousseau’s contentious, contradictory methodology clearly evokes the role of
Socrates, the gadfly immortalized for his prodding attempts to awaken the great, lazy
91
beast that was Athens.
252
In delivering his social criticism as the accusations of a
truth-seeking man, Rousseau likewise urged his peers to know—and question—
themselves and the society of their making. Reform was hardly possible without
honest self-assessment;
253
this was the challenge pressed upon his audience as both
individuals and members of society, and the first stage in reclaiming the hereditary
fruits of our natural goodness.
To paint Rousseau as an Enlightenment-era Socrates is nonetheless hasty.
After all, as Christopher Kelly reminds us, Rousseau was no Socrates.
254
The
Athenian never left his city’s walls save for a brief military expedition and one
conversation with Phaedrus;
255
the Genevan, by contrast, spent most of his life away
from his birthplace. Socrates accepted death by hemlock after his final, ill-fated
apology; Rousseau never even stood trial, fleeing his home before Parisian authorities
arrived to execute the Parlement’s arrest warrant. The most telling difference,
however, is revealed in a simple fact: in discussing his life and writings, Rousseau
was wholly unapologetic.
256
Not only did he justify the supposed misdeeds of his
life, he made their candid revelation a testament of his individual innocence.
Nowhere is this more clear than in his autobiography.
252
As Socrates argues in
The Apology
, “It is literally true (even if it sounds rather comical) that God
has specially appointed me to this city, as though it were a large thoroughbred horse which because of
its great size is inclined to be lazy and needs the stimulation of some stinging fly.” Plato,
The Last
Days of Socrates
, pp. 62-63. For a comparison of how Rousseau’s shamelessness differs from that of
Diogenes the Cynic (the “Socrates gone mad”), see Chapter 4 above.
253
For a fine summary of the scholarly debate surrounding Rousseau’s ability to honestly appraise
himself see: Kelly,
Rousseau
’
s Exemplary Life
:
The “Confessions” as Political Philosophy
, pp. 5-8.
254
Ibid., pp. 10, 54-57, 64-75.
255
See: Plato,
Phaedrus and the Seventh and Eighth Letters
, Walter Hamilton, tr. (New York: Penguin
Books, 1973), p. 21.
256
Socrates’ own “apology” was clearly not devoid of ironic criticism. However, the very fact that he
accepted the verdict of his peers greatly distinguishes him from Rousseau.
92
The subtitle to
The Neuchâtel Preface
257
of
The Confessions
claims to contain
“the detailed account of the events of [the author’s] life, and of his secret feelings in
all the situations in which he has found himself.”
258
In its final printed version,
Rousseau reiterates this declaration as a hypothetical monologue:
Behold what I have done, what I have thought, what I have been. I
have told the good and the evil with the same frankness. I have been
silent about nothing bad, added nothing good… I have shown myself
as I was, contemptible and low when I was so, good, generous,
sublime when I was so.
259
That he presents these lines as the speech he will “loudly” deliver to God on his day
of judgment is of no small consequence. Taken alone, this admission possesses a
notable dearth of humility; when read as a proclamation of merit to “the Sovereign
Judge” it sounds abjectly heretical.
After all, Augustine’s own archetypal
Confessions
eloquently espoused
mankind’s unworthiness in relation to God. In the Saint’s narrative, salvation was a
gift bestowed upon humankind solely by the mercy and grace of God. Man had little
hope of incurring redemption by affecting His will, much less by fearlessly
proclaiming innocence on Judgment Day. For Augustine the hallmark of human
nature was inescapable guilt, a hereditary affliction levied against the descendents of
Adam as punishment for Original Sin. Man could only hope for salvation through
divine mercy, a fate stipulating unassertive deference before God. In stark contrast,
Rousseau suggests that he has nothing to fear (much less regret) on his day of
257
This is the earlier, incomplete draft of
The Confessions
. Of the two completed editions—the
“Geneva” and “Paris” manuscripts—neither is considered definitive. For an explanation see: CW
V.xxxv.
258
The Neuchâtel Preface to The Confessions of J
.
-J
.
Rousseau
. CW V.585; OC I.1148.
259
The Confessions
. CW V.5; OC I.5.
93
judgment.
260
When Kierkegaard later lamented Rousseau’s conspicuous dearth of
Christian humility, he surely had this episode in mind.
261
Was it not pride in a life
well-lived, rather than the burdens of incurable sin, that Jean-Jacques trumpets at the
gates of heaven?
262
Even the non-God-fearing must cringe slightly at Rousseau’s resoluteness.
He is certain of his thoroughness, having revealed “what I have done, what I have
thought, what I have been.” He is convinced of his objectivity (“I have shown myself
as I was”). He suggests that forthrightly admitting his “contemptible” deeds merits
his salvation. And he delivers all of this in a defiant tone, begging the question of
whether or not God, as Rousseau pictured Him, really appreciates anyone raising his
or her voice in His presence. Yet such are the uncompromising terms of Rousseau’s
openness, a value championed from the outset of an autobiography whose author
makes plain that he will hide nothing. The text itself is a realization of this
transparency, a revelation of far more than the mere details of one man’s life. As
Rousseau declares to God, “I have unveiled my interior as Thou hast seen it
Thyself.”
263
The Confessions
is his testament, its readers his witnesses.
264
Such grandiose claims seem to ignore the difficulty of self-revelation. As
Philippe Lejeune reminds us, autobiography poses a distinct methodological problem:
260
See:
Reveries
. (Third Promenade). CW VIII.22; OC I.1019.
261
Søren Kierkegaard,
Journals
(4: 252-253). I address Kierkegaard’s claim in further detail in
Chapter 4.
262
Compare this with Julie’s description of her “Christian end” emboldened by a clear conscience.
Julie
. CW VI.586-589, 598; OC II.713-718, 729.
263
The Confessions
. CW V.5; OC I.5.
264
Although this speech is ostensibly delivered before God such revelation is superfluous because, as
Rousseau reminds us, God sees all. This is therefore a testament made before man, a declaration of
innocence and not (as with Augustine) a public display of humility.
94
“Est-il possible de raconteur sa vie?”
265
Is it, he elaborates, possible to truly recall,
disseminate, and articulate the essence (or even events) of one’s own life? Rousseau
appears untroubled by the subjective complexity of his enterprise. Not only has he
told his life’s story, he has peered within his very soul and “unveiled” his interior,
revealing the insight of a gaze often exclusively attributed to divine beings.
266
Furthermore, he challenges anyone who would cast aspersions. “Eternal Being,” he
requests, “assemble around me the countless host of my fellows: let them listen to my
confessions, let them shudder at my unworthiness, let them blush at my woes. Let
each of them in his turn uncover his heart at the foot of Thy throne with the same
sincerity; and then let a single one say to Thee, if he dares: ‘
I was better than that
man
.’”
267
We must take the term “unworthiness” lightly, for little in these opening lines
suggest anything of the sort. Rousseau is, in fact, claiming precisely the opposite. He
is
worthy: to stand before God, without shame or fear, openly touting the goodness of
his bared soul. He has nothing to fear, not because he was better behaved than the
next man. He has nothing to fear because he
is
like any man—exhibiting faults and
failings, goodness and generosity—with one monumental caveat: he has looked
within himself, and delighted in the natural innocence to which he is closely attuned.
Augustine also looked inward, albeit to a decidedly different conclusion. Soul
searching left the Saint with an ineradicable sense of shame. Bowed under the weight
265
Philippe Lejeune,
L’autobiographie en France
,
Deuxième Édition
. (Paris: Armand Colin, 1998), p.
58.
266
Judith Shklar discusses the all-knowing eye of Wolmar the atheist in great detail in
Men and
Citizens
. The Vicar also claims similar insight: “I can observe and know the beings and their relations,
I can sense what order, beauty, and virtue are, I can contemplate the universe and raise myself up to the
hand which governs it.”
Emile
. E 278.
267
The Confessions
. CW V.5; OC I.5.
95
of his own human sinfulness, he had little hope but to pay deference to the One whose
goodness immeasurably surpassed his own, and dictated the course of his fate. By
contrast, Rousseau drew courage from the insights borne of self-examination.
Unveiling his soul revealed a source of solace in a corrupt world: an individual, a
human being
, whose natural innocence remained intact.
If Rousseau seems prone to self-glorification, his affirmation posed a far more
compelling problem to Catholic authorities. It conveyed an abject heresy
(conspicuous pride in human nature), one that sharply distinguishes
The Confessions
of Rousseau from that of Augustine. Although the works bear substantive and
structural similarities,
268
this fundamental difference divides them: Augustine is
consumed by the certainty of his own guilt, while Rousseau bears little in the way of
regret. More specifically, while Augustine holds himself (as both an individual and a
descendent of Adam) accountable for his sinfulness, Rousseau attributes his own
wavering will to “mitigating factors” beyond his control.
269
Kelly wonderfully
illustrates this schism by contrasting each author’s recollection of youthful
misdemeanors.
270
Reactions worth revisiting, consider first Augustine’s:
I wanted to carry out an act of theft and did so, driven by no kind of
need other than my inner lack of any sense of, or feeling for, justice.
Wickedness filled me. I stole something which I had in plenty and of
268
Lionel Gossman, “The Innocent Art of Confession and Reverie,”
Daedalus
, Vol. 7, No. 103
(Summer, 1978), p. 60. For a careful comparison of these works see: Ann Hartle,
The Modern Self in
Rousseau’s Confessions
:
A Reply to St. Augustine
.
269
Kelly, p. 105.
270
Ibid., pp. 100-108. It is worth noting that Kelly uses a different example, focusing on Rousseau’s
first theft (of asparagus). Kelly uses this to demonstrate the centrality of private property within
Rousseau’s concept of injustice. Readers might compare this with Emile’s experience of ruining a
farmer’s melon seeds by planting his own beans in the same soil. In
Emile
, both parties reach a
mutually acceptable compromise, and thus learn how to navigate the difficult tension between self-
interest and the common good. For Rousseau’s first theft (and candid discussion of his thieving
techniques) see:
The Confessions
. CW V.27-30; OC I.32-36. For the beans and melons incident see:
Emile
. E 98-99.
96
much better quality. My desire was to enjoy not what I sought by
stealing but merely the excitement of thieving and the doing of what
was wrong.
271
The object of theft in question—pears from the tree of a plentiful vineyard—were
carried off in a “huge load… not for our feasts but merely to throw to the pigs.” This
seems a routine juvenile prank, quaint by contemporary standards and harmless
enough to all save the pigs and perhaps a disgruntled farmer. But Augustine
describes his actions as a “foul” example of “wickedness itself,” a testament to his
“lack of any sense of, or feeling for, justice.” His recollections lead him to a
humorless conclusion, one whose gravity far outweighs the physical act itself: “I
loved the self-destruction, I loved my fall, not the object for which I had fallen but my
fall itself. My depraved soul leaped down from your firmament to ruin. I was
seeking not to gain anything by shameful means, but shame for its own sake.”
272
In relatively light-hearted contrast, Rousseau opens his
Confessions
with a
“short and veracious history of all my childish misdeeds.”
273
Admitting to a doting
upbringing (at the expense of his neglected older brother), Rousseau writes that “the
children of Kings could not have been cared for with greater zeal than I was during
my earliest years.”
274
Idealized pampering notwithstanding, he still possessed “the
flaws of my age; I was a babbler, a glutton, sometimes a liar. I would have stolen
fruits, candies, food.”
275
He even recalls “once having pissed into the cooking pot of
one of our neighbors… while she was at church,” a memory that “still makes me
271
Augustine,
Confessions
, II.iv.9, p. 29.
272
Ibid., p. 29.
273
The Confessions
. CW V.9; OC I.10. Although Rousseau elsewhere draws ample attention to his
various misdeeds (including theft), this short paragraph marks
The Confessions
’ first mention of vice.
274
The Confessions
. CW V.9; OC I.10.
275
The Confessions
. CW V.9; OC I.10.
97
laugh.”
276
This rather disgusting (and decidedly unneighborly) episode elicits only
mirth in recollection, and immediately follows a claim of personal innocence oddly
detached from the act to which he has just confessed: “I never took pleasure in doing
harm, damage, in accusing others, in tormenting poor animals.”
277
This comparison underscores the striking discrepancy with which each author
holds himself accountable for his actions. What Augustine identifies as symptomatic
of eternal, hereditary sin, Rousseau dismisses as the tomfoolery of a well-nurtured
lad. What leads Augustine to grueling self-examination and a tortured assessment of
his own depravity leaves Rousseau mildly amused. While Augustine interprets his
theft as a microcosm for the failings of his entire species, Rousseau couches his
“misdeeds” within a declaration of individual goodness, a natural quality cultivated
by his loving upbringing amongst “the best people in the world.”
278
Differences notwithstanding, we must recall that Rousseau’s
Confessions
adhere to Augustine’s formula in one decisive fashion: both works involve “a
repudiation of worldly signs and pleasure, of art and literature; both offer themselves
therefore not as art, but as inmost truth.”
279
The 17
th
Century contributed its share of
such autobiographical literature—most notably Duclos’ 1741
Confessions du Comte
de
***—which, as Lionel Gossman describes, “drew attention to the private
personality, the inner life and time of the individual as opposed to the public events,
the public personalities, and the external chronology and history, to which the
276
The Confessions
. CW V.9; OC I.10.
277
Rousseau’s mention of “tormenting poor animals” seems particularly incongruous, unless we read
in it a sly critique of Augustine (who had, as just noted, confessed to throwing pears at pigs).
The
Confessions
. CW V.9; OC I.10.
278
The Confessions
. CW V.9; OC I.10. Given his upbringing, Rousseau finds the very idea that he
might have possessed a vicious nature to be inconceivable: “How could I have become wicked, since
under my eyes I had only examples of gentleness, and around me only the best people in the world?”
279
Gossman, p. 60.
98
authors… bore witness.”
280
Yet few before Rousseau had paraded their flaws with
such simultaneous straightforwardness and obvious lack of regret. It was the
unrepentant conclusions his quest unearthed, rather than the journey inwards, that
most clearly distinguished him from the confessional tradition. He established a
pattern of admission and qualification (revealing sundry details as pardonable
reactions to external circumstances), shifting the source of accountability from
indigenous failings to exogenous forces. Peer pressure, locked city gates, the sinful
culture of Paris, a desire to please, honest self-assessment, and an overflowing heart
explain (in order) his first theft, his leaving Geneva, his argumentative writings, his
conversion to Catholicism, the abandonment of his children, and his romantic affairs.
In each instance Rousseau exculpates himself, requesting that we judge him on his
intentions rather than his actions.
281
Given his illustrious past, such a standard seems baldly self-serving. After all,
Jean-Jacques was a naughty boy. We know this because he tells us, over many pages
and through many incidents in
The Confessions
. Yet from the outset he initiates a
trend that continues throughout the work: Rousseau is unrepentant. Because he never
sought to harm (the maxim of his “golden rule” from the
Second Discourse
),
282
he
can reflect upon misdeeds with a clear conscience. In examining and revealing his
life he never pleads
mea culpa
, but rather reduces errant behavior to either
developmental immaturity or weakness in the face of exogenous pressures. What
280
Ibid., p. 60.
281
As Rousseau later writes in the
Reveries
(Fourth Promenade): “Only the intention of the speaker
gives them their worth and determines their degree of malice or goodness.” CW VIII.32; OC I.1029.
282
Second Discourse
. CW III.38; OC III.156.
99
Augustine accepted as evidence of an intrinsically sinful nature, Rousseau deflects to
forces external (and thereby foreign or alien) to himself.
By several accounts, this pattern of admission and rationalization presented
the eighteenth century with a radically new vision of self-examination. As Lejeune
writes, “Rousseau est le premier à s’apercevoir qu’il faudrait un ‘langage nouveau,’ et
inaugure un critique des techniques du récit au nom du réalisme subjectif.”
283
This
generous assessment—one made by Rousseau himself in the famous first lines of
The
Confessions
284
—was not shared by those who found his “subjective realism” to be
entirely more subjective than real. As Hérault de Séschelles wrote in 1800,
Rousseau’s was an “errant life,” one “abandonnée aux hasard et aux passions.”
285
This was a common charge amongst critics of the age who found such unbridled
passion ill-suited for an author of his stature, let alone a self-proclaimed bearer of
truth.
286
More recently, Edgar Quinet reiterated and clarified this concern. “Les seuls
livres dangereux pour moi sont ceux où l’on me donne comme réel ce qui ne l’est
pas.”
287
Rousseau was dangerous for precisely this reason. He presented interior
narratives and reverie as objective manifestations of a truth more useful than
283
Lejeune also identifies Rousseau as a founding member of the first generation of a “new form of
biography” which spoke in the first-person, emphasized training, displayed a pre-romanticist
sensitivity, and demonstrated a deep involvement with the contemporary world. Lejeune, pp. 31, 24,
58.
284
“I am forming an undertaking which has no precedent, and the execution of which will have no
imitator whatsoever. I wish to show my fellows a man in all the truth of nature; and this man will be
myself. Myself alone.”
The Confessions
. CW V.5; CW I.5.
285
Hérault de Séschelles,
Voyage à Montbard
, (Paris: 1800), pp. 37-38. Quoted in Bernard Gagnebin,
“L’Étrange accueil fait aux ‘Confessions’ de Rousseau au XVIII Siècle,”
Annales de la Société Jean-
Jacques Rousseau
, Tome 38, 1969-1971 (Geneva: A. Jullien, Éditeur), p. 119.
286
For additional examples of this criticism see: Gagnebin, pp. 108-112, 121-123.
287
Edgar Quinet,
Histoire de mes idées
. (Paris: Flammarion, 1972), p 47.
100
empirical certainty.
288
Echoing de Séschelles, Quinet finds such musings
fundamentally irresponsible: they point us down a slippery slope of self-justification
wherein hyper-subjective “feelings” are conflated with, and presented as, impartial
“reality.” To be fair, Rousseau’s writings offer an anticipatory rebuttal. In an age
ruled by the empire of opinion, the sophisticated logic of philosophers and the
righteous dogma of papists were the real enemies of truth masquerading self-interest
as certainty. Such adroit minds twisted supposedly objective facts to serve
particularist agendas “good only at destructive criticism.”
289
By contrast, Rousseau
argued that his internal sentiments were uncontrived, and served only the common
good. The certainty that Quinet finds perilously misrepresented might
only
be
uncovered by looking inwards.
Amongst Rousseau’s contemporaries, this standard was typically (and in the
case of Voltaire, sarcastically)
290
dismissed as ill-conceived self-justification or
inflated pride; far more menacing were his practical claims. In assailing private
property, ridiculing scientific advancement, rejecting Original Sin, and calling for
religious tolerance and legitimized self-rule, he threatened Church, state and
Academy alike. His image as an anti-hierarchical thinker was only confirmed by
The
Confessions
, a work that defied conventional boundaries of Enlightenment society
288
As Plutarch reminds us, facts are only valuable if they help to instill virtue. In Rousseau’s age, by
contrast, “Critical erudition absorbs everything, as if it were very important whether a fact is true,
provided that a useful teaching can be drawn from it.”
Emile
. E 156; OC IV.415. For further
discussion of this position see Chapter 2 above.
289
Emile
. E 268. The ensuing paragraph further discusses the limits of reason and the utility of
imagination. Delivered by the Vicar, these lines conform to Rousseau’s hierarchy of human faculties.
290
Voltaire’s most famous quip against Rousseau followed the
Second Discourse
: “One acquires the
desire to walk on all fours when one reads your work.”
Letter from Voltaire to Rousseau
, August 30,
1755. CW III.102; CC III.317.157. In a similar spirit, following the
Letter to d’Alembert
, Voltaire
wondered if Rousseau had “become a priest of the Church?” Theodore Besterman, ed.,
Voltaire's
Correspondence
. (Genève: Institut et Musée Voltaire, 1953-1965), XIX.D7864.
101
and elicited shrill “disapproval of the author’s rejection of the neoclassical
discriminations of noble and base, high and low, public and private, tragic and
comic.”
291
As Gossman explains, Rousseau’s “candor about the details of his sexual
life was not in itself shocking; what was, was the seriousness with which he treated
them and asked the reader to treat them,” an approach that blatantly ignored
traditional dismissals of the body as a crass domain ill-suited for philosophical
inquiry.
292
If Jean-Jacques was guilty of indecent exposure,
293
Gossman locates a
democratic impulse in his breach of propriety, a tacit valorization of common (in both
senses of the word) experience. Rousseau’s somatic emphasis also offered a sharp
rejoinder to Augustine, who had urged his audience to look beyond the corporeal
world in anticipation of an eternal life freed from physical desire.
294
For Augustine,
the body was a symbol of man’s most visible weakness (concupiscence) and a
reminder of our fall from grace and distance from God; physical shame was a
logically pious stance given the sins of our flesh. His writings therefore take the body
seriously only as a threat to salvation, an object of denial and repression, and a
hereditary punishment levied upon man for Adam’s transgression. In defying this
tradition Rousseau was not merely titillating his audience or challenging the literary
291
Gossman, pp. 60-61.
292
Ibid., pp. 60-61.
293
I use this term both literally and figuratively. In
The Confessions
, Rousseau admits to a penchant
for seeking out “dark alleys, hidden nooks where I could expose myself from afar to persons of the
opposite sex.” CW V.74; OC I.88-89. He was also charged with slandering the memories of
upstanding
citoyens
such as Mme. de Warens by revealing unsavory details of his romantic affairs. As
M. Geoffrey wrote in the
Année littéraire
(1783, V.vii.99-100), such candor was particularly indecent
for “a Philosopher, a Sage, a Legislator of morals.” For examples of similar critiques see: Gagnebin,
pp. 110-112, 121, 123.
294
This reflects a classical bias of philosophy as well, one epitomized by Plato (for whom wisdom was
an absolute form encumbered by physical trappings). For a thorough overview of this problem see:
Richard Shusterman,
Pragmatist Aesthetics: Living Beauty, Rethinking Art
. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992).
102
standards of a prudish élite. His elevation of somatic concerns reveals, more
pointedly, a repudiation of the denigration of the corporeal life.
295
Dwelling on his
sexual proclivities, uncontrolled appetites, and sundry weaknesses was necessary
given his commitment to revealing the truth. But such exposure also taught an
affirmative lesson, one accessible to those of all walks of life: fear not our corporeal
sins, for they are only skin-deep.
296
At heart of Rousseau’s argument is a faith in the innocence of human nature.
Rather than teaching us to humble ourselves as woefully inadequate creatures before
God, he urged us to follow his lead in
The Confessions
, to draw courage from our
status as divine creations. Jean-Jacques’ candor was therefore calculated or
purposeful in that it lighted a hopeful path to reform. It was also deeply problematic,
for it left him open to charges of blatant hypocrisy and gave detractors a convenient
means of dismissing him.
297
His authority as a moral critic lay in his relative lack of
culpability. But by unveiling the sundry details of his life he presented the portrait of
an individual objectively ill-suited to exculpate himself.
In his own defense, Rousseau reiterated his guiding principals (natural
goodness, and a pursuit of truth that demanded unmitigated revelation) while
deflecting the significance of his actions. In a world of corrupting attachments, he
ascribed guilt to external sources. The radical implications of his rationalization
295
From his very first
Discourse
, Rousseau had argued that “the needs of the body are the foundations
of society.”
First Discourse
. CW II.5; OC III.6.
296
In this, Rousseau falls between Machiavelli and Nietzsche who both recognized “slavishness” in
Christian morality. See:
Discourses on Livy
, II.2.159.
297
Rousseau was particularly insulted by this charge. As he asks Beaumont, “Why would I be a
hypocrite, and what would I gain from being one? I attacked all particular interests, I aroused all
factions against me, I upheld only the cause of God and humanity, and who cares about that?”
Rousseau suggests that he would have been far less prosecuted if, following the
philosophes
, “I had
openly declared myself in favor of atheism.”
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.50; OC OV.964.
103
cannot be understated. In it we find a neophyte theory of political victimization, one
that attributes blame to unjust social forms rather than intrinsically flawed beings.
298
Nurture, not nature, is the culprit in this equation. As an individual raised in idyllic
circumstances, Rousseau was uniquely nurtured to follow his nature, an exemplar of
goodness particularly resistant to society’s influence. His personal innocence
therefore supports his claim of ontological innocence: the life he revealed to the
public offered testament to his species’ inherent worth.
This is the “truth” put before the audience to whom he bears his very soul, an
argument pressed upon his peers. After all, Rousseau was far more anxious about
being misjudged by men than God. If he begins his
Confessions
by testifying before
the Sovereign Judge, he reminds us of the superfluity of this revelation. God sees us
for who we are; this is why Rousseau is unafraid to assert his innocence in His
presence. By contrast, human judgment is far more fallible, our reason woefully
limited.
299
This boundary is acutely evident in our comprehension of divinity, a
failing discussed at length by the Savoyard Vicar in
Emile
. The Vicar chastises
humankind for believing “we possess intelligence for piercing… [such] mysteries,”
when in fact “all we have is imagination.” It is “through this imaginary world [that]
each blazes a trail he believes to be good. None can know whether his leads to the
goal [of salvation]. Nevertheless we want to penetrate everything, to know
298
Inge labeled this “sentimental humanitarianism” Rousseau’s single worst contribution to the
modern world, a “mawkish travesty of Christianity which transforms morality by basing it solely on
pity, and transfers guilt from the individual to the state under which he lives. Man is always innocent,
the government always guilty.” (Inge, p. 250) Arthur Melzer offers a more judicious assessment,
noting that Rousseau “initiates the philosophic tendency, which has dominated almost all subsequent
thought, to understand the human problem in terms of historical, social, or environmental causes rather
than natural or divine ones.” Melzer,
The Natural Goodness of Man,
p. 17.
299
Compare with René Descartes’
Sixth Meditation
in
Meditations on First Philosophy
,
Revised
Edition
, John Cottingham, ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
104
everything.”
300
Although raised by the Vicar, this concern articulates a problem later
posed in
The Confessions
.
301
Not only do we believe ourselves capable of
comprehending God, we parade these “imaginary” visions as righteous, intolerant
truths. This vanity is twofold: because the limits of our reasoning prevent us from
clearly comprehending the divine state we personalize God, reducing Him to an
extension of our own particular predilections and worldviews.
302
As Rousseau
elaborates,
In general, believers make God as they are themselves, the good make
him good, the wicked make him wicked; the devout who are spiteful
and choleric see only Hell because they would like to damn the whole
world: loving and gentle souls hardly believe in it.
303
The reduction of God to the self-image of the worshipper is therefore morally
ambiguous. It can have wicked (for the wicked) and just (for the just) consequences.
Given his scathing criticism of Catholic dogma, Rousseau likely had papists in mind
as those who “damn the whole world” to Hell. But he also poses a positive
alternative, the “loving and gentle souls” who place faith in a benevolent deity.
To illustrate this, Rousseau presents Mme. de Warens as a unique figure in a
corrupt age, a “soul without bitterness, which could not imagine God as vindictive
and always wrathful, saw only clemency and mercy where the devout saw only
300
Emile
. E 268.
301
This argument is also consistent with the
Second Discourse
. In this case, artificial desires
(encouraged by
amour-propre
) are self-destructive because they surpass both our natural needs and
capacities for fulfillment.
302
In this, Rousseau follows Malebranche who similarly preached the generality and simplicity of
God. For a thorough study of this connection see: Riley,
The General Will Before Rousseau
.
303
The Confessions
. CW V.192; OC I.228-229. It is worth noting that the pressure exerted by the
Church was overwhelming, affecting even the noble Fénelon: “one of the astonishing things from
which I cannot recover is to see the good Fénelon speak about it in his
Telemachus
, as if he truly
believed it: but I hope that he was lying then; for in the end however truthful one may be, one certainly
must lie sometimes when one is a Bishop.” In the
Dialogues
, Rousseau describes Fénelon as one of
the few virtuous men who “did honor to modern times,” praise affirmed by
Telemachus
’ role in
Emile’s education. CW I.158; OC I.863-864.
105
justice and punishment.”
304
A woman of rare gentleness, de Warens’ vision of divine
mercy lies in sharp contrast with the vengeful figure propagated by the Catholic
Church. She hardly believed the Author of all things had endowed His creations with
an irreparably sinful nature. Rousseau’s beloved
maman
found failing not in God,
but in His misleading portrayal by men: “It seemed to her that Scripture was
explained too literally and too harshly,” and when discussing specific articles of the
Bible “it happened that she saw [each] completely differently from the Church, even
while always submitting to it.”
305
More specifically, she believed Purgatory—not
eternal damnation—offered a suitable fate for the wicked, a group “always very
vexing both in this world and in the other.”
306
What begins as a passing (and seemingly innocent) plea for theological
moderation immediately leads to a radical renunciation. As Rousseau hastily
concludes, “one sees that the whole doctrine of original sin and redemption is
destroyed by this system [of Purgatory], and the basis of vulgar Christianity is shaken
by it, and that at least Catholicism cannot subsist.”
307
The certainty of his conclusion
is matched only by the suddenness of its intrusion into the text. Rousseau, it appears,
is eager to remind readers that Adam’s supposed legacy of hereditary sin is a fallacy
propagated by men, one debunked with as little effort as the passing mention of
Purgatory. In one fell swoop, he claims a startling accomplishment: crippling
Catholicism by shaking the “vulgar” foundations upon which it rests.
304
The Confessions
. CW 192; OC I.229.
305
The Confessions
. CW 192; OC I.229.
306
Given the rosy glow that often shades Rousseau’s recollections of de Warens, his account may be
inaccurate. If this were the case, Rousseau would be repeating the crime imputed to him by Christophe
de Beaumont of presenting impious beliefs in “chimerical voices,” a charge discussed in greater detail
below.
307
The Confessions
. CW 192; OC I.229.
106
Rousseau’s antagonism towards the Church reflects what Ernst Cassirer
described as a principal fear of Enlightenment philosophers, that to “change religion
into mere opinion… [is to] deprive it of its real moral and political force.”
308
Unlike
his
philosophe
peers, however, Rousseau shared this concern without abandoning his
faith in God. More strongly, he insisted that religious associations provided a
necessary moral foundation for virtuous democratic societies.
309
Yet papal faith
should not be considered genuine; it denuded religion of its ethical and practical
value, supplanting divine truths with vicious myths. Nowhere was the blasphemy of
their orthodoxy more evident than in the narrative of Original Sin.
* * * * *
The innocence of which Rousseau speaks is surely personal, yet its
implications extend far beyond the author himself. This is evident in his self-
justification: Jean-Jacques, more natural than his denatured peers, was subsequently
more innocent. In ontological terms, this position assumes that humankind is good by
nature and not tainted by Adam’s fall. Far from it, we have corrupted ourselves,
introducing evils that place us at sharp odds with our divinely-crafted natures.
Rousseau’s rebuke of hereditary guilt lies at the heart of
The Confessions
, just as it
rests at
Emile
’s center.
310
It was also the reason he fled Paris in 1762: he escaped an
arrest warrant issued by the Parlement and applauded by the Church, both of whom
308
Cassirer,
The Philosophy of the Enlightenment
, p. 165. This claim is demonstrable in the influence
of Bayle upon the
philosophe
circle, particularly Diderot (and his
Encyclopédie
article on Pyrrhonism).
309
See Chapter 5 below.
310
Not only does Rousseau describe the
Profession
as
Emile
’s moral core, it appears literally halfway
through the text.
107
viewed his renunciation of Original Sin as a threat to spiritual and political order.
311
What might strike contemporary readers as a dry and distant debate was a life-
changing event for Rousseau. In this, he was not alone; roughly fourteen centuries
prior, the Christian ascetic Pelagius rejected hereditary guilt to equally momentous
consequences.
312
Rousseau’s indebtedness to Pelagius is typically assumed. This was true as
early as 1765 when, in passing, the Abby Laurent François identified Pelagianism in
Rousseau’s diminution of grace as a means of salvation.
313
More recently, Karl Barth
described the Genevan’s doctrine of natural goodness as “the apogee of humanist
Pelagianism,” while Jean Guehenno located a Pelagian legacy within Rousseau’s
mistrust of metaphysics, his “sentimental” emphasis upon freedom, and the righteous
tenor of his social criticism.
314
Pierre Burgelin saw shadows of Pelagius in Saint-
Preux’s defense of human liberty, a figure commonly assumed to be modeled after
Rousseau himself. And Jean-François Thomas—in the only work devoted
exclusively to this relation—concluded that Rousseau was indeed a semi-Pelagian,
albeit one very much indebted to Molinism and Jesuit writings on freedom and
311
Extrait des Registres du Parlement
, June 9, 1762. CC XI.A254.262-266.
312
Accused of heresy in Jerusalem in 415, newly condemned for his
De libero arbitrio
(
On Free Will
)
in 416, Pelagius was finally condemned and excommunicated in 417 by Pope Innocent I, a ruling
confirmed by Innocent’s successor Zosimus in 418. This verdict was influenced by the verbose wrath
of Augustine, who wrote volumes against Pelagius and went so far as to demand his public censure: “I
do not hesitate at once to affirm that such a man [as Pelagius] ought to be removed from the public ear,
and to be anathematized by every mouth.” Augustine,
A Treatise Concerning Man’s Perfection in
Righteousness
, Chapter XXI (44) in
Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers of the Christian Church: Volume
V
, Benjamin B. Warfield, tr. (Grand Rapids, MI: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 1971), p.
176.
313
Robert Derathé, “Jean-Jacques Rousseau et le Christianisme,” in
Revue de Métaphysique et de
Morale
(1948), p. 379.
314
Jacques-François Thomas,
Le Pélagianisme de J
.
-J
.
Rousseau
. (Paris: Librairie Nizet, 1956), pp. 8-
9.
108
grace.
315
Although many have labeled Rousseau’s concept of innocence Pelagian,
few have explored the association in any detail.
316
Correcting this paucity allows us
to both impart coherence to an oft-bandied yet ill-defined term, and shed light upon
the seeds from which Rousseau’s most controversial theological paradox grows.
317
Before discussing parallels between Pelagius and Rousseau, we might begin
with an obvious difference. Unlike the well-documented Genevan, the figure of
Pelagius is marked by relative obscurity.
318
We know little of the details of his life
save that he was well-educated and born some time after 350 AD, probably in
Britain.
319
We also know that he was an exile of sorts. He left his birth land for
reasons unknown
320
and arrived in Rome
circa
380 AD, becoming a spiritual advisor
315
In the late sixteenth century in works such as
Concordia liberi arbitrii cum gratiae donis
(
The
Harmony of Free Will with Gifts of Grace
), the Jesuit theologian Molina attempted to reconcile a
concept of free will with his faith in divine justice and mercy. He presented a notably optimistic view
of human nature, one that allowed man sufficient grace to aspire towards redemption. For a thoughtful
exposition of the Jesuit influence upon Rousseau during his stay in Montmorency see: Gilbert Py,
“Jean-Jacques Rousseau et la Congrégation des Prêtres de l’Oratoire de Jésus,”
Annales de la Société
Jean-Jacques Rousseau
, Tome 38 (Geneva: A. Jullien, 1969-1971), pp. 127-153.
316
More striking than the typical brevity with which this connection is raised are the thoughtful studies
that fail to even mention Pelagius’ name. Allan Bloom examines Rousseau’s concept of goodness in
great length. P. M. Masson’s unrivaled three-volume
La Religion de J. J. Rousseau
work investigates
the heretical foundations of Rousseau’s theological thought. And in
The Natural Goodness of Man
,
Arthur Melzer discusses Rousseau’s radical renunciation of Original Sin. In all of these studies,
Pelagius is conspicuously absent.
317
I do not mean to suggest that Rousseau was steeped in (or even directly influenced by) the writings
of Pelagius, but rather argue that a study of Pelagianism illuminates a problem central to Rousseau: the
concomitant concern with spiritual and secular values. A figure who also expressed deep faith in
heretical terms, Pelagius is far more helpful on this count than Augustine (who similarly described sin
as a self-incurred disease, yet concluded that only God might cure us).
318
“The writings of the Pelagians are notoriously anonymous,” Peter Brown notes, “and so are their
supporters.” Much of what we know about Pelagius and his followers comes from writings assumed to
be theirs, references in works of their contemporaries (most notably Augustine and Jerome), and a
small number of primary sources (governmental and ecclesiastical documents). B. R. Rees attributes
Pelagianism’s “poor press” to this scarcity of definitive primary sources. See: Peter Brown,
Religion
and Society in the Age of Saint Augustine
. (London: Faber and Faber, 1972), p. 208; and
The Letters of
Pelagius and His Followers
, B. R. Rees, tr. (Suffolk: The Boydell Press, 1991), p. 1.
319
See:
Pelagius’s Commentary on St. Paul’s Epistle to the Romans
, Theodore de Bruyn, tr. (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1993), p. 10; Rees,
Pelagius: A Reluctant Heretic
. (Suffolk: The Boydell Press,
1988), pp. xii-xiv.
320
The two most common explanations are career ambitions and a spat with his father. Rees, Ibid., p.
xiii.
109
to Roman Christian aristocrats.
321
Pelagius entered Rome during a period of wealth
and flamboyance but also insecurity and striving, one ruled by a gluttonous
aristocracy both habituated to and increasingly disgusted with its routine
decadence.
322
The practical consequence of such ambivalence was a demand for
guidance. Nobles were “in constant need of mentors—from teachers of literature to
father-confessors”—to instruct them to rise above the concupiscence so rampant
amongst their socially-illustrious ranks.
323
It was an age “clouded with doubts” not simply about the plight of the
privileged, but around a core tenet of the Catholic Church: the origin and legacy of
the Fall of the human soul, a subject of protracted (and indeterminate) writings,
debate and dialogue.
324
Before Pelagianism “there had been little open debate about
matters of doctrine and belief.”
325
Indeed, history suggests that the Catholic Church
lacked a “coherent body of doctrine tried, tested and refined in the furnace of
321
This was a popular practice amongst the wealthy and spiritually ambitious. Brown, pp. 186-188.
322
Brown describes the privileged class of statesmen and orators as “a heterogeneous and, in part, a
nondescript body of men.” Yet they could hardly be accused of dullness, baring all the exaggerated
marks of ancient decadence: conspicuous consumption, lusty indiscretions, a propensity for gambling,
and a distaste for scholarly work. Roman élites were also notably competitive, “determined to live
according to… distinctive standards of excellence”—an aspiration guided by both “their sense of high
birth” and the desire to distinguish themselves from their peers. There was also a vocal conservative
backlash reared by the pagan orator Symmachus (who upheld strict protocol and ceremony in the
Senate) and the Christian Senator Jerome (who no less disapprovingly beseeched his peers to “learn
from me a holy arrogance”). Ibid., pp. 186-188.
323
In becoming a spiritual advisor, Pelagius was simply joining a well-established and increasingly
popular profession. The neo-Platonist Plotinus, an influence upon the young Augustine, was one of the
earliest figureheads of this tutorial tradition. Ibid., p. 188.
324
Ibid., p. 220. The free-will debates had spanned over 200 years. Augustine’s eventual victory over
Pelagius was aided more by the Saint’s tireless public sermons and growing influence than unified
doctrinal consensus amongst Church fathers.
325
Rees,
The Letters of Pelagius and His Followers
, p. 10. Rees goes so far as to suggest that “[t]here
had been no heresy before this one, if one excludes Priscillianism which arose in the peripheral area of
Spain.” One must also exclude Arianism (an early fourth century movement rejecting the divinity of
Jesus Christ), as well as smaller sects such as the Manichaeans and Gnostics (from which
Priscillianism is derived). It is worth noting that in his 1690
Dictionnaire Universel
, Furetière names
only three examples of heretics: Arius, Luther and Calvin; Pelagius is conspicuously absent. See:
Furetière’s
Dictionnaire Universel
, Tome II.
110
controversy.”
326
Although Pelagius and his followers claimed to be
integri Christiani
(authentic Christians), prior to his writings there existed little consensus as to what
this term actually meant.
327
If by the late fourth century orthodox dogma was still a work in progress,
328
a
definitive position had begun to coalesce around Augustine’s influential sermons on
free will. According to Augustine, Scripture is unequivocal on the origins and
transmission of sin:
Genesis
3 describes the fall of man as punishment for Adam’s
errant appetite; 1
Corinthians
15 teaches that Christ died for our sins and was raised
by God as a redeemer; and
Romans
5 describes sin as an ineradicable hereditary
disease. Adam was held accountable for tasting fruit from the tree of knowledge
because he was told not to (by God) and free not to (through an act of will). In falling
to temptation, Adam revealed the weakness of a will whose divided nature stood in
hideous contrast to the unified Divine will. Such was the legacy passed on to his
species. Fatally self-subverting and the source of enduring shame, our very natures
predisposed us to stray from God’s righteous example.
329
At first glance, Pelagius’ teachings may seem compatible with this
Augustinian (and decidedly un-Rousseauist) world-view. He urged his brethren to
live a stern, disciplined life, envisioning a Christian community connected by what
Peter Brown describes as an “icy puritanism,” hither unto binding ideals of propriety
326
Rees, Ibid., p. 10.
327
Brown, pp. 192-3.
328
Rees,
Pelagius: A Reluctant Heretic
, p. 56. For a summary of the two main theories of Original Sin
in the second and third centuries—what N. P. Williams describes as “Hellenic, once-born or
minimizing” and “African, twice-born or maximizing”—see pp. 57-58.
329
Under this view, our only hope for redemption lay after earthly penance was paid, at the
postmortem, grace of the Being whose laws we are incapable of following. For Augustine, then, the
first penalty of Adam’s eternal gaffe—mortality—also provides our only hope. Because Original Man
had sinned, all men must die; yet because we all lay at God’s mercy, salvation might only be attained
following death.
111
and piousness, secular conduct aimed at spiritual elevation consummated by the grace
of Christ.
330
Yet Pelagius understood asceticism as redemptive corporeal vigilance
rather than shameful self-denial. Far from discounting human action, he granted
somatic reform a central role in the grueling struggle towards Christian elevation.
Unlike Augustine, for whom salvation depended solely upon God’s grace, Pelagius
shifted the burden of redemption upon man’s meager shoulders. Where Augustine
understood human free will as the catalyst for sin, Pelagius located the means of
training ourselves to live righteously. Where Augustine saw grace as the only means
of transcending Adam’s legacy, Pelagius identified an antidote independent of God’s
will. Where Augustine felt sin permeate the marrow of his soul, Pelagius saw a
superficial (albeit ubiquitous) condition—bad habits reified through the ages—in
need of a corporeal remedy.
331
Pelagius therefore presented a twofold offense to the
teachings of Augustine: not only did he soften the impact of the Fall, he claimed that
Christians should and could raise
themselves
.
332
Because man was not irreparably
330
Brown, p. 194. Although Rees affirms the severity of the Pelagian “evangelical, salvationist and
didactic” vision (
Letters
, p. 12), not everyone agrees. De Bruyn reminds us that “[f]or most Christians,
both clergy and laity, the regime advocated by zealots was too severe. Even those who approved of
asceticism in general were disturbed by extreme manifestations.” He describes Pelagius as just such a
moderate, citing his position on a heated dispute of Manichaean origins: whether or not Christians
should eat meat. Pelagius carefully abstains from passing categorical judgment, instead claiming that
scripture does not explicitly require vegetarianism of the faithful. De Bruyn overly signifies this
concession, one that hardly conforms to Pelagianism’s broader Christian “ascetic program” that
“envisaged not the end of corporeal existence, but rather the extirpation of the passions which obscured
the vision of God.” Furthermore, this isolated instance of compromise does not even distinguish
Pelagius from Augustine who arrived at a similarly cautious defense of meat-eating in the
Confessions
(xxxi.45). See: De Bruyn, pp. 2-7, 12, 15; and
Pelagius
’
Commentary on the Romans
14:1-23, pp.
140-144.
331
Rousseau shared a skeptical view of habit. In an author’s note to
Emile
he describes a vicious
circle: “The appeal of habit comes from the laziness natural to man, and that laziness increases in
abandoning oneself to habit.” Both he and Pelagius faced criticism for failing to explain habituated sin
in light of natural goodness. See: De Bruyn, p. 24;
Emile
. E 160n.
332
This divergence is acutely evident in their competing beliefs about baptism. Augustine preached
the necessity of infant baptism as the first stage of redeeming ourselves in God’s eyes. By contrast,
Pelagius understood baptism as a commitment to self-conscious change, one only meaningful to
mature adults. Rousseau makes a similar argument about religion in
Emile
, stressing the need
112
burdened with guilt, human agency in addition to divine grace could cleanse us of our
sins.
In works such as the
Commentary on St. Paul’s Epistle to the Romans
and
On
Nature
, Pelagius argued that sin was not a hereditary condition but a habituated lapse
in judgment.
333
Predating Rousseau’s description of denatured man, he argued that
corruption “lives as a guest” in humankind “as an accidental quality, not a natural
one.”
334
Drawing upon the metaphor of an unwanted disease attacking a host-victim,
Pelagius claimed that “carnal habit,” far from characterizing human desire, actually
“opposes the will.”
335
As with Rousseau, corruption distorts and disserves (rather
than epitomizes) our divinely-crafted natures.
In framing this argument, Pelagius draws upon a vision of a tough-but-fair
God, a figurehead who would hardly set us up to fail by establishing a standard of
conduct impossible to fulfill.
336
Nor would He levy eternal punishment upon
creatures whom He both loved and created in His image. Rather than wait for
salvation in an afterlife, we must rethink the mantra of accountability that plays so
prominent a role in Augustine’s narrative of the Fall. We must bear responsibility for
our own actions, using Adam’s model as a lesson of malfeasance rather than proof of
introduce God only after human beings are developmentally capable of comprehending Divinity (“for
if he learns it sooner than he ought, he runs the risk of never knowing it”). E 257.
333
It is in these works that Pelagius developed what Augustine later described as the “three principal
heads in the Pelagian heresy”: the denial of Original Sin; the contention that “the grace of God
whereby we are justified is not given freely, but according to our merits”; and the argument that “in
mortal man, however holy and well doing, there is so great righteousness that even after the washing of
regeneration [Baptism], until he finishes this life of his, forgiveness is not necessary to him.” His
influence as a spiritual leader had grown with his role as a pedagogue, but it was not until
approximately 405 AD, after these works had reached Augustine’s disapproving eye, that he became
embroiled in controversy. See: Augustine,
Against Two Letters of the Pelagians
, Book III, Chapter 24.
(Warfield, p. 414)
334
Commentary on the Romans
, 7:17. (De Bruyn, p. 104)
335
Ibid., 7:18, p. 104.
336
Readers should note this parallels the position Rousseau approvingly attributes to de Warens in
The
Confessions
.
113
irredeemable guilt. As Pelagius concludes, “I myself have provided myself with this
compulsion.”
337
If “I” am the agent, it follows logically that “I” must take
responsibility for curing my self-incurred concupiscence.
To support his case, Pelagius distinguished between rational instinct and
irrational desire. “Habitual desires, or the persuading of the enemy” is opposed to
“
The law of my mind
. Namely, of natural conscience, or of the divine law, which
resides in the mind.”
338
In terms clearly presaging Rousseau, “divine law” is
inscribed upon our “natural conscience.” Wickedness results from a failure to
comprehend and follow this order, an estrangement whose redress requires the
cultivation of our natural God-given ability to determine right from wrong. As
Pelagius argues, we must retrain our wills, not damn our natures, because “the will
was arraigned, not the nature, which God created in such a way that it [was able] not
to sin.”
339
Carnal impulse does not mask the stench of irredeemably tainted flesh; it
rather reveals the force of habit and the prevalence of poor decision-making amongst
humankind. As with Rousseau, a stifled conscience is no sign of irredeemable fault;
it rather punctuates the need to reawaken this innate faculty through meaningful
corporeal reform.
Augustine found in these urgings utter blasphemy.
340
Defining corruption as
habitual rather than necessary reduced sin to a problem of human “negligence,” one
curable through an act of will.
341
Where Augustine saw “confirmed invalids,”
337
Commentary on the Romans
, 7:20. (De Bruyn, p. 104)
338
Ibid., 7:22, p. 107.
339
Commentary on the Romans
, 8:3, (De Bruyn, p. 107).
340
Augustine found this position Scripturally unsound. Citing
Psalms
12:1 & 8; 41:4, he reminds us
that the “[t]he nature of which our author [Pelagius] speaks is corrupted.” Augustine,
On Nature and
Grace
, Ch. 57 (Warfield, pp. 140-141).
341
Ibid., Ch. 14 [XIII] (p. 125).
114
Pelagius envisioned humankind “like the man found wounded on the road from
Jerusalem to Jericho—saved from certain death… [yet] resigned to spending a
lifetime of precarious convalescence in the Inn of the Catholic Church.”
342
Neither
might be confused with a libertine, and despite Augustine’s portrayal Pelagius was
hardly an unqualified optimist. Like Rousseau, he recognized the ubiquity of societal
corruption and—in a tone reminiscent of Seneca
343
—the difficulty of reform. Yet as
with Rousseau, Pelagius looked squarely in the eyes of what he believed was a
decadent culture, and challenged the
necessity
of this decline. Where Rousseau later
invoked our divinely-crafted nature as evidence of inherent innocence, so did
Pelagius take recourse in our intrinsic God-given goodness. Rousseau and Pelagius
agreed that
men
had made a mess of a divine creation;
man
must therefore halt his
self-incurred fall, reorient himself to follow his conscience with the knowledge that
sin was actually the logical and finite consequence of improvident action.
Because God is the “Author” of nature (a phrase Rousseau also frequents),
natural order must reflect his unquestionable goodness. Pelagius applied this logic to
human nature which, as a divine creation, possessed the capacity for goodness. Yet
in making the ontological claim that humankind is naturally good and not necessarily
342
Brown, p. 203.
343
The Stoic sage, according to Seneca, is of so rare character that one “perhaps springs into existence,
like the phoenix, only once in five hundred years.” (
Epistulae Morales
xiii.1) Sages are beings
hardened to external circumstances and worldly forces who follow a moral code drawn in accordance
with nature. Despite manifold difficulties, Seneca advises that the human will, can, with enough effort,
achieve this plateau through personal fortification, an act of will that overcomes “weakness of the
mind,” (
De Ira
II.ii.2) and an indifference to forces beyond one’s control, a state Martha C. Nussbaum
labels “radical detachment” (both external resistance and internal command of one’s emotions). For a
discussion of this term see:
The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic Ethics
,
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994), pp. 363-364. On Tertullian’s reference to Seneca as
“often one of us [Christians]” see: A. A. Long,
Hellenistic Philosophy
,
Second Edition
. (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1986), p. 236. Saint Jerome also makes this connection in
Against
Rufinus
. See:
Dogmatic and Polemical Works
, John N. Hritzu, tr. (Washington, DC: The Catholic
University of America Press, 1965), p. 210.
115
beholden to sin, Pelagius rendered an unqualified blasphemy: he negated the value of
Jesus Christ’s sacrificial death on the cross. As Augustine lamented, the mere
possibility
of man’s innocence “renders the cross of Christ of none effect.”
344
Denying man’s hereditary guilt as descendents of Adam did not merely disserve the
obedience we owe God (as the only possible cause of our redemption), or brazenly
raise our self-estimation; it meant that “Christ [is] dead in vain.”
345
Jesus could not
have died a sacrificial death (bearing a brutal punishment for our sins) were we not all
sinners. By reducing a crime of eternal guilt to one of temporal circumstance, human
goodness renders the terms of his sacrifice moot.
Not that Pelagius was lenient. If eating from the tree of knowledge did not
elicit eternal punishment, God’s vengeance was still indisputably fierce. After all,
Adam received “the death-penalty for breaking one single prohibition; and even he
was less to blame than us, for he did not have the great benefit of the previous
execution of a human being to deter him.”
346
To understand Pelagius’ feud with
Augustine as a conflict over severity is therefore inaccurate; Augustine was far more
agitated by Pelagius’
emphasis
.
Let us recall the Saint’s two distinct albeit related lines of criticisms: first,
Pelagianism gives man an inflated sense of the value of his actions; and second, so
doing demeans the role of God in our lives. If humankind is endowed with
conscience, free will and a universal potential to rise above sin, this might also
suggest a democratic vision of egalitarian reform. However, asceticism—a practical
remedy for societal decay—posed a challenge few would except, one that conformed
344
Augustine,
On Nature and Grace
, Ch. 21, p. 127. See also: Ch. 9, p. 124.
345
Ibid., Ch. 9, p. 124.
346
Brown, p. 204.
116
to a rigid and grueling vision of the Christian life prone, much like Seneca’s quest for
enlightened wisdom, to failure. In the end, and unlike Rousseau, Pelagius was neither
republican nor Protestant; he was simply “looking for better Christians and not for a
more democratic form of government.”
347
In the
Social Contract
, Rousseau makes a strong distinction between “the
Religion of man and that of the Citizen” and demands that we choose.
348
For
Pelagius, there was hardly a choice; Christians, not citizens, were his overarching
concern. Furthermore, “he sincerely believed that his teaching was orthodox and
consistent with that [Catholic] Church’s tradition.” As B. R. Rees argues, this belief
guided his protracted self-defense: “it was in order to prove [his orthodoxy] to his
critics that he allowed himself to become involved in an arduous and prolonged
controversy for which he was by ethos and training quite unsuited.”
349
If, as Rees
concludes, we should consider Pelagius a “reluctant” heretic we might also consider
him a “stubborn” heretic, so certain was he of his own piety.
Whatever the qualifying adjective, Pelagius’ heresy is indisputable in
hindsight. He maintained theological doctrine in opposition, or held to be contrary, to
the Roman Catholic Church. Yet Brown reminds us that Augustine—not Pelagius—
“abandoned a great tradition of Western Christianity” by denying that “it was ever
possible for a man to slough off his past; neither baptism nor the experience of
conversion could break the monotonous continuity of a life that was ‘one long
temptation.’”
350
By contrast, Pelagius adhered to the “the idea that conversion and
347
Rees,
A Reluctant Heretic
, p. 112.
348
The Social Contract
. CW 219; OC III.464.
349
Rees,
A Reluctant Heretic
, p. 131.
350
Brown, p. 200.
117
initiation could make a total break in personality,” a belief that W. H. C. Frend
describes as “the Christianity of discontinuity.”
351
In claiming that man might be
reborn through an act of will, Pelagius revealed himself to be “the last, the most
radical, and the most paradoxical exponent” of the ancient faith.
352
And here we return to this chapter’s initial concern. Heresies are, by
definition, paradoxical; they are defined by the rejection of commonly held truths.
Pelagian heterodoxy offers an additional paradox—one charged to Rousseau as
well—by using traditional values as the foundation of radical revisionism. Both men
preached ontological innocence as a heuristic catalyst to reform; both refused to
abandon core Christian doctrines including the existence of an afterlife and the moral
guidance provided by God (as revealed in either the natural world or scripture); and
both set redemptive doctrines against the backdrop of pessimistic realism (stark
sociopolitical critique). Most significantly, both insisted upon the righteousness of
their paradoxical faiths, maintaining the conviction that they were more pious than
their many detractors.
* * * * *
If the messages were similar, the messengers were less so. Pelagius was an
austere ascetic who lived as he preached. Rousseau was neither sternly disciplined
nor God-fearing, facts that did not prevent him from passing judgment. Curiously,
for a thinker wedded to the idea of innocence life appeared anything but. Man may
be intrinsically good but the society of his making was undoubtedly corrupting, “fit
351
Ibid., p. 200. See also: W. H. C. Frend,
Martyrdom and Persecution in the Early Church
(1964), p.
402.
352
Ibid., p. 200.
118
only for making double men.”
353
In evoking this image Rousseau hearkened back to
Augustine, whose
Confessions
provides the
locus classicus
of divided individualism.
As the Saint described, “in the process of deliberation a single soul is wavering
between different wills” that pull us towards mutually exclusive loves of spiritual and
carnal gratification.
354
This morbid, painful condition “pull[s] apart the human heart”
and debilitates the mind.
355
Yet for Augustine, such was man’s lot: this internalized
“struggle of myself against myself” was a manifestation of the “‘sin which dwelt in
me,’ sin resulting from the punishment of a more freely chosen sin, because I was a
son of Adam.”
356
By contrast, Rousseau understood such contradictory impulses as a struggle
between nature and artifice, natural instincts and social pressures,
man
(as divine
creations) and
men
(as socially distorted creatures):
Swept along in contrary routes by nature and by men, forced to divide
ourselves between these different impulses, we follow a composite
impulse which leads us to neither one goal nor the other. Thus, in
conflict and floating during the whole course of our life, we end it
without having been able to put ourselves in harmony with ourselves,
and without having been good either for ourselves or for others.
357
Far from epitomizing human nature, divergent wills oppose it.
358
In broader terms,
“conflict and floating” is symptomatic of a disconnect between the way things truly
353
Emile
. E 41.
354
Augustine,
Confessions
, VIII.x.23, p. 149.
355
Ibid., VIII.ix.21 & VIII.x.24. pp. 148 & 150.
356
Ibid., VIII.xi.27 & VIII.x.22, pp. 152 & 149. Augustine’s reference is to
Romans
7: 17, 20.
357
Emile
. E 41.
358
In works such as
The Social Contract
and
Poland
, Rousseau sought to reform society by
legitimizing political institutions. Yet in
Emile
he seems far more withdrawn, suggesting we raise “a
man… uniquely for himself.” Such “negative” or defensive education protects individuals from a
corrupt world while cultivating their natural goodness. “To form this rare man” we must “prevent
anything from being done.” (E 41) As he elaborates in his
Letter to Beaumont
, “If man is good by his
nature, as I believe I have demonstrated, it follows that he remains so as long as nothing foreign to
himself spoils him. And if men are wicked, as [papists] have gone to the trouble of teaching me, it
follows that their wickedness comes from elsewhere. Close the entrance to vice, then, and the human
119
are by nature and the way they are made to seem in a denatured world. For Rousseau,
this condition was a source of tremendous angst, one which he repeatedly confronts
throughout his works.
359
It was also, as Jean Starobinski believes, a preoccupation
rooted in personal experience.
360
As a youth in Bossey, Rousseau was a house servant to the Lambercier
family. Alone in a room where his master’s comb was found broken and “no one but
myself had entered,” he appeared guilty of vandalism.
361
Despite the weight of
evidence and the Lamberciers’ dogged interrogations, he “stubbornly persisted” in
denying any wrongdoing. “I would have suffered death and I was resolved to do so,”
he thunders, rather than suffer the indignation of taking responsibility for a crime he
had not committed.
362
As his vivid recollection of an incident that occurred more
than fifty years prior makes plain, Rousseau was still haunted by the memory of this
false accusation. It marked his conversion from naive innocent to outraged victim. In
his own words, he was transformed from
a child always governed by the voice of reason, always treated with
gentleness, equity, kindness; who did not even have the idea of
injustice, and who suffers such a terrible one for the first time from
precisely the people he loves and respects the most. What a reversal of
heart will always be good. On this principle, I established the negative education as the best or rather
as the only good one. I show how all positive education, no matter how it is pursued, follows a path
contrary to its goal. And I show how one tends to the same goal and how one reaches it by the route I
have sketched.” CW IX.35; OC IV.945.
359
Here I follow Starobinski, who cites “transparency” as Rousseau’s primary unifying concern. This
manifests itself both positively (as baring his soul in
The Confessions
, for example), and negatively—
as the rejection of mediating bodies in religion (the church), politics (representative democracy), and
the arts (theater).
360
It is worth noting that Kelly disagrees: “Contrary to what Starobinski claims, Jean-Jacques feels no
split between appearance and truth. He feels a split between the Lamberciers’ past gentleness and their
present injustice.” (Kelly, p. 94) However, these points are not mutually exclusive. The “present
injustice” of denatured society, for example, also indicates a failure to act in accord with our “true”
natures.
361
The Confessions
. CW V.16; OC I.18. For Rousseau’s full account see: CW V.16-17; OC I.18-20.
362
The Confessions
. CW V.16-17; OC I.19.
120
ideas! what disorder of feelings! what an upheaval in his heart, in his
brain, in all his little intellectual and moral being!
363
Falsely impugned guilt left him with a “feeling of violence and injustice,” one that
“has remained so deeply engraved on my soul, that all the ideas related to it give me
back my first emotion.”
364
An enduring source of indignation, Rousseau drew upon a
general hatred from this particular experience: “my heart is inflamed at the spectacle
of all unjust actions—whatever their object might be and wherever they are
committed—just as if their effect fell on me.”
365
This was a point of no return, one
which evoked a bitter conclusion: “From that moment I ceased to enjoy a pure
happiness, and even today I feel that the remembrance of the charms of my childhood
stops there.”
366
Under Rousseau’s adroit pen, a broken comb adopts the significance of
Adam’s fall from Eden. It is an event replete with crime, accusation, punishment,
breach of trust, epiphany, and a sudden and enduring loss of innocent bliss—with one
crucial caveat. He insists that his Original Sin was a crime in appearance only: “Jean-
Jacques appears to be guilty although in fact he is not. He appears to lie when in fact
he is sincere.”
367
His experience becomes a sacrificial testament of integrity, one
where an innocent victim bears the individual burden of a general failure to determine
truth from opinion. Furthermore, an error of this sort carries dire consequences.
363
The Confessions
. CW V.17; OC I.19.
364
The Confessions
. CW V.17; OC I.20.
365
The Confessions
. CW V.17; OC I.20.
366
The Confessions
. CW V.18; OC I.20.
367
Starobinski,
Transparency and Obstruction
, p. 7.
121
Rousseau was forced not simply from his masters’ home, but from the very “serenity
of my childlike life.”
368
In Edenic terms, this rude awakening forces us to consider the significance of
a Fall in which man is not guilty. It was an idea first developed (in relatively
impersonal terms) in the
Second Discourse
where, as with Jean-Jacques himself,
humankind begins in a natural state of benign bliss and falls victim to apparently
arbitrary, corrupting circumstances beyond its immediate control. As in
The
Confession
s, an underlying claim of innocence appears to contradict empirical
evidence. In each instance, readers must dismiss the facts Rousseau himself
introduces—be it ubiquitous corruption or his sole access to a broken comb—in order
to arrive at a deeper truth. Whether the subject is Jean-Jacques or humankind, readers
are asked to sympathize with the innocent wronged.
Rousseau repeats this request in
Emile
, lamenting that sometimes a youth “is
chastised before he is able to know his offenses or, rather, to commit any.”
369
Yet by
falsely imputing malice we actually awaken it. “We fill up his young heart at the
outset with the passions which later we impute to nature.”
370
This unfounded
ascription epitomizes societal corruption for two reasons: it attributes intrinsic guilt to
innocent creatures, and plants “the development of the artificial seeds” of
amour
propre
and malicious self-interest. A child so reared grows to become a dangerous
man, a “slave and tyrant, full of science and bereft of sense, frail in body and soul
alike.” Inept and proud, a carrier of vice, this unnatural product “becomes the basis
368
The Confessions
. CW V.18; OC I.20.
369
Emile
. E 48.
370
“After having taken efforts to make him wicked, we complain about finding him so.”
Emile
. E 48.
122
for our deploring human misery and perversity.”
371
Such a dour conclusion is,
however, misguided. “He is the man of our whims; the man of nature is differently
constituted.”
372
At heart of this argument is an undying faith in the ontological innocence of
humankind, a connection Rousseau reinforces by suddenly directing us to his most
provocative Pelagian treatise,
The Profession of Faith of the Savoyard Vicar
.
373
The
Profession
itself makes an equally conspicuous entrance into
Emile
. Neither taught to
the prized pupil nor told in the tutor’s voice, it follows an introductory caveat: “I am
not propounding to you the sentiment of another or my own as a rule. I am offering it
to you for examination.”
374
The “other” in question is the “decent ecclesiast,” a
nameless Vicar
375
who begins his soliloquy with a refrain suspiciously familiar to
Jean-Jacques himself. “Do not expect either learned spectacles or profound reasoning
from me,” he warns. “I am not a great philosopher, and I care little to be one. But I
sometimes have good sense, and I always love the truth.”
376
This humble sense of limitation immediately leads the Vicar to question his
obligations as a Catholic cleric. As he admits, “it was not long before I sensed that in
371
Emile
. E 48.
372
Emile
. E 48. Hobbes, for one, got it wrong when he “called the wicked man a robust child.” This
is somewhat misleading. As Hobbes wrote in the Preface to
De Cive
, children are pre-moral only
because they are not bound by duty: “because not having the use of reason, they are totally exempt
from duties. If they continue to do the same things when they are grown up and have acquired the
strength to do harm, then they begin to be evil and to be called so. Thus an evil man is rather like a
sturdy boy, or a man of childish mind, and evil is simply want of reason at an age when it normally
accrues to men by nature governed by discipline and experience of harm.” Hobbes,
On the Citizen
, p.
11.
373
Amidst a discussion of innate moral sense, conscience, and natural love of goodness, Rousseau
writes: “See hereafter the Profession of Faith of the Savoyard Vicar.”
Emile
. E 67
374
Emile
. E 260.
375
The Vicar is based on two
Abbés
Rousseau encountered (and admired) as a youth: “the decent M.
Gaime” and “the most gentle of men,” M. Gâtier. See:
The Confessions
. CW V.76-77, 99-100; OC
I.90-92, 118-119.
376
Emile
. E 266.
123
obliging myself not to be a man I had promised more than I could keep.”
377
His sense
of imminent failure—of the unnatural demands pressed upon him—caused him to
question his piety. “I was in that frame of mind of uncertainty and doubt that
Descartes demands for the quest for truth.” This “disturbing and painful” state, one
“hardly made to last,” compounded his misgivings of doubt itself. “How can one
systematically and in good faith be a skeptic,” he asks? “I cannot understand it.
These skeptic philosophers either do not exist or are the unhappiest of men.”
378
Rousseau knew perfectly well that such philosophers did exist, and—from
Pyrrho to Montaigne—were famous for their preternatural calm. But the Vicar’s
sensational claim establishes his creed’s guiding principle: given the limits of human
reasoning, piety cannot rest upon reason alone. As evidence he points to the
“diversity of sentiments,” the variety of religious opinions whose sheer numbers
subvert any one’s claim to possessing an exclusive truth.
379
Their incongruity reveals
not righteousness but “the insufficiency of the human mind” guided by excessive
“pride.” “Insufficiency” prevents us from truly comprehending God, while hubris
deludes us into thinking otherwise. Divine mysteries are nonetheless impenetrable:
[They] surround us on all sides; they are above the region accessible to
the senses. We believe we possess intelligence for piercing thee
mysteries, but all we have is imagination. Through this imaginary
world each blazes a trail he believes to be good. None can know
whether his leads to the goal. Nevertheless we want to penetrate
everything, to know everything. The only thing we know is how to be
ignorant of what we cannot know. We would rather decide at random
and believe what is not than admit that none of us can see what is. We
are a small part of a great whole whose limits escape us and whose
Author delivers us to our mad disputes; but we are vain enough to
377
Emile
. E 367.
378
Emile
. E 367-368.
379
Emile
. E 268. On this point, Rousseau’s influence can be seen in William James’
The Varieties of
Religious Experience
.
124
want to decide what this whole is in itself and what we are in relation
to it.
380
Definitive knowledge of the divine is, however, nothing short of self-delusion. More
specifically, such claims are both dangerous and unnecessary. Dangerous because, as
the history of the Catholic church illustrates, dogmatic certainty leads to violent
intolerance; and unnecessary because they do not cultivate true piety. The Vicar
accepts as “true” only that which he feels “in the sincerity of my heart.” Everything
else is left in a sort of spiritual purgatory, a state of “uncertainty without rejecting it
or accepting it and without tormenting myself to clarify it if it leads to nothing useful
for practice.”
381
Admitting not to “know why the universe exists,” he approaches it “like a man
who saw a watch opened for the first time,” admiring the craftsmanship without
understanding the mechanics.
382
He is also certain that its parts “are moving in
harmony only for a common end which it is impossible for me to perceive.” But such
380
Emile
. E 268. Compare this with the Vicar’s remarks on the difficulties of contemplating God
(285), and the tutor’s description of God as an “incomprehensible Being who embraces everything,
who gives motion to the world and forms the whole system of beings, Is neither visible to our eyes nor
palpable to our hands; He escapes all our senses.” (255). This position adheres to a traditional
voluntarist belief in the incomprehensibility of God, one shared by thinkers as diverse as Augustine,
Ockham, Duns Scotus and Malebranche.
381
Emile
. E 270. The Vicar’s skepticism sets the stage for his diminution of belabored reasoning.
Although conscience (our moral compass) never errs, the faculty of comparison is prone to error—it
relies upon “understanding, which judges the relations, mixes its errors in with the truth of the
sensations, which only reveal the objects.” (E 271) Descartes reached a similar conclusion in his
Sixth
Meditation
, but understood man’s “confusion” as a consequence of his nature, “a combination of mind
and body… that is bound to mislead him from time to time.” The Vicar modifies this dualism: man’s
dividedness is a consequence of
denaturization
.
Pitié
and
amour-de-soi
are the sole impulses guiding
our will in the natural state, and they never lead us astray. In the
Second Discourse
, Rousseau
describes willing as a “purely spiritual act.” Perception and sentiment defines man’s first state, while
willing, desire and fear “will be the first and almost the only operations of his soul.” (CW III.26-27;
OC III.142-143.) As evidence, he offers two articles of faith. First, “a will moves the universe and
animates nature.” (E 273) And second, because “moved matter” reveals a causal act of will, “matter
moved according to certain laws shows me an intelligence.” (E 275) A retreat to conscience therefore
offers a point of communion with God, a deference to the “intelligence” that orders the natural world.
See also: Descartes,
Meditations on First Philosophy
, VI.88, p. 61.
382
Emile
. E 275.
125
absolute comprehension is unnecessary. Where reason requires certitude, faith is
affirmed through simple observance of a divine order, one revealed “not only in the
heavens which turn, not only in the star which gives us light, not only in myself, but
in the ewe which grazes, in the bird which flies, in the stone which falls, in the leaf
carried by the wind.”
383
Such is evidence of a “supreme intelligence” neither
“healthy mind” nor “unprejudiced eyes” can refute.
384
Lest we think him an incurable romantic or a long-gone hippie, the Vicar turns
his gaze to the real world. The results shock him from his starry-eyed sentimentality.
“What a spectacle! Where is the order I had observed? The picture of nature had
presented me with only harmony and proportion; that of mankind presents me with
confusion and disorder!... Beneficent Being, what has become of your power? I see
evil on earth.”
385
As with Pelagius, the Vicar concludes that corruption is self-
inflicted. “Our sorrows, our cares, and our sufferings come to us from ourselves.
Moral evil is incontestably our own wor
.”
386
Of this he is certain.
Man, seek the author of evil no longer. It is yourself. No evil exists
other than that which you do or suffer, and both come to you from
yourself. General evil can exist only in disorder, and I see in the
system of the world an unfailing order. Particular evil exists only in
383
Emile
. E 275. Invocations such as these have led many to associate Rousseau with Deism, the
belief that religious sentiment is inborn and not acquired strictly through revelation or Church
teachings.
384
By contrast, theological “sophisms” are not simply contestable; they lead to debilitating doubt and
actually make it “impossible to recognize the harmony of the beings and the admirable concurrences of
each piece in the preservation of others.” (E 275) This “harmony”—the ordered expression of divine
will—justifies the Vicar’s celebration of humanity: “content with the place in which God has put me, I
see nothing, except for Him, that is better than my species.” As with Pelagius, evidence of man’s
innocence “lies precisely in his being a peculiar, special creature of God.” Robert F. Evans,
Pelagius:
Inquiries and Reappraisals
. (New York: The Seabury Press, 1968), p. 92. For a discussion of this
“new idealism” (which, along with radical skepticism and humble realism informs Rousseau’s concept
of natural goodness) see: Melzer, p. 26.
385
Emile
. E 278.
386
Emile
. E 281. (My emphasis.)
126
the sentiment of the suffering being, and man did not receive this
sentiment from nature: he gave it to himself.
387
Evil is a corporeal affliction, one that exists only as a finite sentiment. Attributing its
cause (and absolution) to the will of God disserves both the Author and His creation
alike. To do so “is to want Him to do my work while I collect the wages for it. Not
to be contented with my condition is to want no longer to be a man, it is to want
something other than what is, it is to want disorder and evil.”
388
If, as the Vicar
laments, we were only “satisfied to be what we are, we would not have to lament our
fate.”
389
Rather than embrace our divinely-crafted natures we seek “imaginary well-
being,” a process that “give[s] ourselves countless real ills.” An argument familiar to
Rousseau’s readers, the unfettered pursuit of unnatural desires has disastrous
consequences. As the Vicar makes plain, “take away our fatal progress, take away
our errors and our vices, take away the work of man, and everything is good.”
390
A return to God is clearly in order. But if, as the Vicar confides, “the more
effort I make to contemplate His infinite essence, the less I can conceive it,” how
might we commune?
391
Given the limits of reason we must look within. “Let us
return to ourselves,” the Vicar exclaims! “Let us examine, all personal interest aside,
387
Emile
. E 282. In stressing the coherence of a general divine order Rousseau again follows
Malebranche.
388
Emile
. E 294. Following Pelagius, because our sins are self-inflicted their remission does not
require divine grace. As the Vicar makes plain, “death is the remedy for the evils you do to
yourselves; nature”—and therefore God—“did not want you to suffer forever.” (E 281) Note that this
both precedes and supports Rousseau’s “purgatory” argument from
The Confessions
.
389
Emile
. E 281. As in
The Confessions
, the
Discourses
, and the
Letter to d’Alembert
, man’s desire to
live beyond his natural limits is the source of significant woe.
390
Emile
. E 282. Rousseau began
Emile
with a similar claim: “Everything is good as it leaves the
hands of the Author of things; everything degenerates in the hands of man.” (E 37)
391
Emile
. E 286.
127
where our inclinations lead us.”
392
It is this very examination that, as with Rousseau,
leads him to affirm his natural goodness:
All the morality of our actions is in the judgment we ourselves make
of them. If it is true that the good is good, it must be so in the depths
of our hearts as it is in our works… If moral goodness is in
conformity with our nature, man could be healthy of spirit or well
constituted only to the extent that he is good. If it is not and man is
naturally wicked, he cannot cease to be so without being corrupted,
and goodness in him is only a vice contrary to nature.
393
Here is a Pelagian manifesto of notable assertiveness and simplicity. Man is either
good or bad. “If he were made to do harm to his kind, as a wolf is made to slaughter
his prey… virtue would leave us with remorse” because it would contradict our God-
given natures.
394
But it does not. We are gratified by the happiness of others, find
beneficent acts more agreeable than wicked ones, and possess “admiration for heroic
actions” and “raptures of love for great souls.” Furthermore, the Vicar notes,
“[a]mong so many inhuman and bizarre cults, among this prodigious diversity of
morals and characters, you will find everywhere the same ideas of justice and
decency, everywhere the same notions of good and bad.”
395
Such sentiments attest to
an underlying universal order, one to which all men are naturally drawn regardless of
their social differences. As creatures of the same God, we are beholden to the same
divine law.
396
“If one had listened only to what God says to the heart of man,” the Vicar
argues, “there would never have been more than one religion on earth.”
397
Because a
392
Emile
. E 287.
393
Emile
. E 287.
394
Emile
. E 287.
395
Emile
. E 288.
396
Emile
. E 286.
397
Emile
. E 295.
128
“just heart is the true temple of the divinity,” one accessible to “every country and
every sect,” the “true duties of religion are independent of the institutions of men.”
398
Specific forms of worship are therefore somewhat arbitrary, based upon
contingencies such as birthplace and familial tradition, but not the embodiment of
exclusive truths.
399
A positive argument for religious tolerance, this also serves as a
renunciation of revelation. “View the spectacle of nature; hear the inner voice,” he
urges. “Has God not told everything to our eyes, to our conscience, to our judgment?
What more will men tell us?”
400
Not only is human testimony superfluous, it is also
demeaning.
[R]evelations have only the effect of degrading God by giving Him
human passions. I see that particular dogmas, far from clarifying the
notions of the great Being, confuse them; that far from ennobling
them, they debase them; that to the inconceivable mysteries
surrounding the great Being they add absurd contradictions; that they
make man proud, intolerant, and cruel; that, instead of establishing
peace on earth, they bring sword and fire to it. I ask myself what good
all this does, without knowing what to answer. I see in it only the
crimes of men and the miseries of mankind.
401
As in
The Confessions
, man’s meddling only corrupts religion’s spiritual and practical
value. “As soon as peoples took it into their heads to make God speak, each made
Him speak in its own way and made Him say what it wanted.”
402
Reduced to a
reflection of human passions and “absurd contradictions,” God becomes a puppet of
those who arrogantly assume to represent him.
398
Emile
. E 311.
399
Nature “made itself respected on earth and seemed to relegate crime, along with the guilty, to
heaven.”
Emile
. E 288-289. Compare this with the Vicar’s dismissal from E 296: only “a mad
vanity” could convince us “that God takes so great an interest in the form of the priest’s costume, in
the order of the words he pronounces, in the gestures he makes at the altar, and in all his
genuflections.” External worship “is purely a question of public policy” and civil harmony. By
contrast, true piety—“that of the heart”—is nourished internally.
400
Emile
. E 295.
401
Emile
. E 295.
402
Emile
. E 295.
129
The Vicar suggests his provocative creed should only inspire “reasons for
doubt,” and demands that we “seek the truth” for ourselves. This qualification
precedes a condemnation of those who, by contrast, believe “that they alone are
enlightened, true, and of good faith,” and “imperiously subject us to their peremptory
decisions.”
403
It is at this point that we find Rousseau’s most revealing intrusion in
his own voice, in an author’s note. He takes the Vicar’s critique as an opportunity to
air his own grievances, specifically against papists. “Are the people who traffic in
religion those who are religious? All the crimes committed among the clergy, as
elsewhere, do not prove that religion is useless, but that very few people are
religious.”
404
Thus an argument for tolerance ends as an attack against the self-
anointed mediators of God’s will.
405
A claim of innocence that contradicts Catholic orthodoxy; a strike against the
vanity of those who purport to comprehend and represent God; a defense of religious
tolerance and condemnation of fanatical dogmatism.
406
All this coupled with a
forthright accusation against the self-proclaimed faithful who prove “that very few
people are religious.” Should there be any surprise that this work was anathematized?
What began as a skeptical quest to uncover simple answers to complicated questions
unfolds as a renunciation of Original Sin and Catholic authority alike. Rousseau was
403
Emile
. E 295, 312. For a extended discussion of this claim see: Ch. 4, “Rousseau as Recluse.”
404
Emile
. E 313.
405
This was precisely the line of argumentation Rousseau adopted in
The Social Contract
’s discussion
of Civil Religion. Readers should consult Chapter 5 below for a detailed examination.
406
However, in typically paradoxical fashion, Rousseau actually defends fanaticism as preferable to
irreligion: “fanaticism, although more deadly in its immediate effects than what is today called the
philosophic spirit, is much less so in its consequences.” In a tone presaging Nietzsche, Rousseau
laments that “indifference to the good” born of the “philosophic spirit” is the greater of two evils, one
that “quietly saps the true foundations of every society.”
Emile
. E 312.
130
soon held accountable for these heresies and forced, yet again, to defend his
innocence.
* * * * *
Reaction to
Emile
was unprecedented. As P.-M. Masson notes, it marked the
first time the publicly-sold work of a celebrated author approved by the censor
Malesherbes had elicited such severe reprobation.
407
Rousseau’s critical attitude
towards Catholicism hardly distinguished him from the
philosophes
of his age, but his
writings lacked their “ordinary hypocrisies” and “irony.”
408
He attacked papal
authority as neither an atheist nor a libertine, but a champion of genuine religious
faith. The resultant scandal was so loud, the refutation so imperious, “que la justice
fut obligée si sévir.”
409
Ruthless it was: on June 7, 1762
Emile
was brought before
the general assembly and publicly burned in Paris four days later. On June 19, the
Genevan government burned both
Emile
and
The Social Contract
following the
Conclusions du Procureur général
.
410
And on July 18,
Emile
was banned in notably
tolerant Amsterdam.
411
In
The Confessions
Rousseau professed obliviousness to these impending
storms, although his private correspondence suggests otherwise.
412
He had previously
expressed anxiety over
Emile
’s reception in a November 30, 1761 letter to
407
Masson,
La Religion de J. J. Rousseau
, vol. III, p. 47.
408
Ibid., vol. III, p. 47.
409
Masson,
“La profession de foi du Vicaire Savoyard” de Jean-Jacques Rousseau
,
édition critique
.
(Fribourg-Paris, 1914), pp. liii-liv.
410
Conclusions du Procureur général sur deux livres intitulés de Contract Social & de l’Education
.
CC XI.A266, pp. 298-301. See also:
la Condamnation
. CC.A267, pp. 301-302.
411
Les Etats de Hollande et de West-Frise à la Municipalité d’Amsterdam
. CC XI.A268, pp. 302-303.
412
See:
The Confessions
. CW V.481-482; OC 575.
131
Malesherbes.
413
And in a May 29, 1762 letter to his publisher Michel Rey, he
described
The Social Contract
as a work that would be neither “admitted nor tolerated
in France.”
414
Reaction to his political treatise was decidedly more muted, most
threatening to the Genevan Council who viewed it as a radical critique of their own
government
415
yet greeted in France as “one of many abstract books on the
philosophy of law, which, because of its obtuse nature, could not have a great
influence on the public.”
416
Emile
, however, received no such reprieve.
Marcel Françon described its censure as an “injustice and cruelty without
equal,” arguing that the charge of blasphemy was a “pretext” obscuring the malicious
machinations of “Voltaire et son clan pour perdre Rousseau.”
417
This was, of course,
the argument Jean-Jacques presented in his autobiography. So convinced was he of
both his own piety and a “Holbachian” plot against him that he reduced
Emile
’s
condemnation to an elaborate personal vendetta.
418
Françon’s accord
notwithstanding, Rousseau’s conspiracy theory is at best incomplete: it hardly
acknowledges the unmistakably heretical substance of his condemned work.
419
413
Quoted in Marcel Françon, “La condamnation de ‘l’Émile,’”
Annales de la Société Jean-Jacques
Rousseau
, Tome 31 (Geneva: A. Jullien, 1946-1949), p. 227.
414
Quoted in Ibid., p. 233.
415
Rousseau’s most elaborate response to the Genevan Council’s condemnation of the
Social Contract
is found in his
Letters Written From the Mountain
.
416
“During the commotion caused by the
Emile
and the religious ideas that it contained,” Rosenblatt
continues, “the
Social Contract
had practically been ignored in France.” Helena Rosenblatt,
Rousseau
and Geneva
, p. 271.
417
Françon, p. 244
418
The Confessions
. CW V.482;OC I.576.
419
In its entry on
Heresy
, the 1957 edition of
A Catholic Dictionary
makes an apparent concession to
Protestants: “Such Protestants as are in good faith and sincerely desirous of knowing the truth are not
heretics in the formal sense, inasmuch as they do not pertinaciously reject the Church’s teaching.
Their heresy is material only—their tenets are in themselves heretical, but they are not formal heretics:
they do not incur the guilt of heresy.” This conclusion is indebted to Aquinas, for whom the heretic’s
guilt was incurred by willfully contradicting orthodoxy: “certain doctors seem to have differed either in
matters the holding of which in this or that way is of no consequence, so far as faith is concerned, or
even in matters of faith, which were not as yet defined by the Church; although if anyone were
obstinately to deny them after they had been defined by the authority of the universal Church, he
132
As we have already seen, the
Profession of Faith
renounced Original Sin,
Catholic revelation and papal authority alike. Espoused by the Vicar, it nonetheless
developed views Rousseau presented elsewhere in his own voice. This concordance
did not escape his most vociferous critics. As the Archbishop of Paris Christophe de
Beaumont commented, the use of an “assumed character who serves him as
mouthpiece” was a literary sleight-of-hand, the thinly-veiled attempt of an author to
distance himself from what he surely knew were inflammatory paradoxes. By
renouncing Original Sin “through the organ of a chimerical character,” Rousseau was
not simply blasphemous; he was also a coward.
420
More gravely, Beaumont’s
Pastoral Letter
presents the author of
Emile
as
living proof that the “
perilous days
” of Saint Paul’s predictions had come to pass.
421
An exemplar “
of corrupt spirit and perverted Faith
,” Rousseau’s disbelief took many
forms: the “light, pleasant, frivolous style” of novels (such as
Julie
) aimed at stoking
the imagination, seducing the mind, and corrupting the heart; the feigned “air of
profundity and sublimity” in works like
The Second Discourse
that pretend “to go
back to the first principles of our knowledge… in order to shake off a yoke that,
according to it, dishonors humanity, even the Divinity”; “enraged” attacks “against
Religion’s zeal,” and misguided defenses of “universal tolerance.” Sometimes,
Beaumont concludes, disbelief unites
all these diverse languages, it mixes the serious with playfulness, pure
maxims with obscenities, great truths with great errors, Faith with
blasphemy; it undertakes, in a word, to harmonize light with shadows,
would be deemed a heretic.” (
Summa Theologica
, 2.2.11) Although Rousseau claimed to be in good
faith, he clearly rejected Catholic orthodoxy; his heresy was therefore more than merely “material,”
and indisputable even by these relatively generous standards.
420
Pastoral Letter of His Grace the Archbishop of Paris
. CW IX.8.
421
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.3. Beaumont’s Biblical reference is to 2
Timothy
3:1-4, 8.
133
Jesus Christ with Belial. And such is especially, My Very Dear
Brethren, the object that appears to have been proposed in a recent
Work, which has as its title
Emile
,
or on Education
.
422
Emile
was a perverse amalgam, a paradoxical pairing of God and Satan that paraded
purity as obscenity, error as truth, heterodoxy as faith. It was also woefully
impractical, proposing “a plan of education that, far from agreeing with Christianity,
is not even suited to making Citizens or Men.”
423
Rousseau spoke in “contradictory
language,” ignored empirical evidence (“an infinite number of facts, even prior to that
of Christian Revelation, that it would be absurd to doubt”),
424
and exhibited “glaring
bad faith.”
425
He slandered the papacy (“in clouds, he cunningly imputes to us
dealings that dishonor reason”),
426
Catholics (as evidenced by the “revolting…
language he puts into the mouth of a supposed Catholic,” the Vicar), and monarchs
(“Kings who are the images of God”).
427
In short, Rousseau posed a theological
and
political threat. A heretic who
took “pleasure in poisoning the sources of public felicity, by inspiring maxims that
tend only to produce anarchy and all the calamities that follow from it,”
428
he
undermined both Church and state. These ruling bodies were intimately linked and
literally above reproach, their authority synonymous with that of Christ Himself, the
“one
through whom Kings reign
.”
429
Because “
there is no Power that does not come
422
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.3.
423
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.4.
424
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.9-10.
425
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.12. Beaumont repeats his charge of “bad faith” on pp. 10 & 13.
426
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.10.
427
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.13.
428
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.14.
429
“The constitution of Christianity, the Spirit of the Gospel, even the errors and the weakness of the
human mind lead to the demonstration that the Church established by Jesus Christ is an infallible
Church.”
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.13. Beaumont’s Biblical reference is to
Proverbs
8:15.
134
from God
,”
430
Beaumont argued, anyone who “
resists the Powers resists the order of
God
.” As with Adam, such offenders “
draw damnation upon themselves
.”
431
Rousseau was therefore guilty on two counts. As an author, he refused to submit to
this “Doctrine of a Book that cannot have been invented by men.”
432
And as a human
being, he carried the legacy of “the deplorable fall of our first Father,” the “striking
mixture of greatness and baseness, of zeal for truth and taste for error, of inclination
to virtue and penchant to vice” that defines our very nature.
433
According to Beaumont, only a “delicate and laborious” Christian education
might uproot, “as much as possible, those vicious inclinations that are the sad effects
of our hereditary corruption.”
434
In rejecting Original Sin, Rousseau disagreed.
Because corruption was self-inflicted, healing began by first
embracing
our natures;
the Catholic Church actually impeded convalescence by preaching that sin was
intrinsic.
435
The Archbishop bristled at this “erroneous, impious, blasphemous, and
heretical” suggestion.
436
By renouncing orthodox precepts as unnecessary to
salvation, Beaumont concluded that Jean-Jacques had sealed his own eternal fate.
430
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.14. Beaumont’s Biblical reference is to
Peter
2:17 which teaches us to
“
Fear god
,
respect the King
.”
431
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.14. Beaumont’s Biblical reference is to
Romans
13:1-2.
432
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.11-12.
433
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.4-5. If Adam’s legacy imparts any lesson it is “
to live in this world with
temperance according to justice and with piety, while waiting for the beatitude for which we hope
!”
(15) Beaumont’s Biblical reference is to
Titus
2:12-13. For Paul’s pedagogy, see also 2
Timothy
4:1-2.
434
Pastoral Letter
. CW IX.14-15.
435
As Beaumont warns: “Woe to you, woe to society, if your children were brought up in accordance
with the principles of the Author of
Emile
! Just as there is nothing but religion that has taught us to
know man, his greatness, his misery, his future destiny, it also belongs to it alone to form his reason, to
perfect his morals, to procure for him a solid happiness in this life and in the other.”
Pastoral Letter
.
CW IX.14.
436
Beaumont’s final ruling reads very much like the Parlement’s court order: “We condemn the said
Book [
Emile
] as contained an abominable doctrine, suited to overturning natural Law and to destroying
the foundations of the Christian Religion; establishing maxims contrary to Evangelical Morality;
tending to disturb the peace of States, to stir up Subjects against the authority of their Sovereign; as
containing a very great number of propositions respectively false, scandalous, full of hatred against the
Church and its Ministers, departing from the respect due to Sacred Scripture and the Tradition of the
135
As Rousseau’s response made clear, he did not take such damning lightly.
His retort—the November 18, 1762
Letter to Beaumont
—opened, provocatively
enough, with a quote from Augustine: “Pardon me if I have spoken too freely—it was
not to dishonor you, but to defend myself. I have relied on your seriousness and
prudence, because you can measure how great [a] necessity you imposed on me of
answering you.”
437
If Rousseau felt forced to respond he did so with great verve,
issuing a rebuttal more than four times the length of the
Pastoral Letter
. He began
his passionate defense by recalling the facts that led to his censure:
A Genevan has a Book printed in Holland,
438
and by degree of the
Parlement of Paris this Book is burned without regard for the
Sovereign whose authorization it bears. A Protestant poses objections
to the Roman Church in a Protestant country, and a warrant is issued
against him by the Parlement of Paris. A Republican states objections
against the monarchic State in a Republic, and a warrant is issued
against him by the Parlement of Paris. The Parlement of Paris must
have strange ideas about its dominion and believe itself the legitimate
judge of the human race.
439
In one terse paragraph, Rousseau defends his legal rights, suggests a violation of
sovereign jurisdiction,
440
and attributes this abuse to an unholy alliance between
Church, erroneous, impious, blasphemous, and heretical. In consequence We very expressly forbid all
people of our Diocese to read or possess said Book, under penalty of law.”
Pastoral Letter
. CW
IX.16.
437
The lines Rousseau uses as his dedicatory epistle to the
Letter to Beaumont
are taken from
Augustine’s
Epistle 238
. This was the first of two letters written to Pascentius, an Arian count and tax-
collector known for his vocal attacks against Catholicism and the “energetic” (read: greedy) execution
of his office. Following a public debate with Augustine that he claimed to have won (although he
presented little in the way of argument save personal opinion), Pascentius ignored further
correspondence from Augustine. The context of this letter makes its invocation all the more
inflammatory. Not only did Rousseau appropriate Beaumont’s most beloved theologian, he has
usurped a letter written against a heretic. Note also that the preceding line—“truth must necessarily
prevail, whether we deny it or admit it”—expresses a markedly Rousseauist faith in the righteousness
of truth against the delusion of opinion.
Saint Augustine: Letters
,
Volume V (204-270)
, Sister Wilfrid
Parsons, tr. (New York: Fathers of the Church, Inc., 1956), p. 209.
438
This was the only version authorized by Rousseau for printing. Françon, p. 234.
439
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.23; OC IV.929.
440
As we will discuss in Chapter 5, this jurisdictional boundary was crucial to Rousseau’s Civil
Religion as well.
136
Church and state. He raises issues of discrimination and tolerance, legitimate
authority, and the rights individuals possess in relation to unjust institutions. And he
concludes that Catholic, monarchal Parisian authorities possessed neither the legal,
political nor moral authority to censure a work printed with the permission of the
Holland government and written by a Protestant, republican Genevan.
441
But they did
and, as with the comb incident, the fate of the free world seemed to hinge on their
ruling. “I do not know how this fits with international law, but I know very well that,
with such procedures, every man’s freedom and perhaps his life is at the mercy of the
first Printer.”
442
Although the implications of this case extend far beyond Jean-Jacques
himself, Rousseau cannot help but lament his own particular fate. Having taken up
his pen “only for the good of my fellows,” his reward was the encroachment of
bailiffs and an arrest warrant. At a time “when I hoped that my life’s troubles were
about to end,” he rues, “my greatest misfortunes began.”
443
This was not the first
moment Rousseau described as his life’s worst,
444
but we may here allow him his
histrionics. For once, he was not exaggerating.
The censure of
Emile
indeed marked new heights of persecution, and it was
due in large part to the
Profession of Faith
. Yet rather than defend this work as his
own, he initially attempted to absolve himself of responsibility. Rousseau was the
441
As Rousseau had written in an earlier draft, “I admit to you that it is not without surprise that I see
myself summoned in some manner before you, and that I would not have understood very well on what
grounds J.J. Rousseau, Citizen of Geneva, would have been accountable for his writings to a catholic
Prelate.”
Letter to Beaumont
(Fragment 5). CW IX.86; OC IV.1012.
442
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.23; OC IV.929.
443
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.22; OC IV.929.
444
In addition to the comb incident, Rousseau rued his epiphany en route to Vincennes, his fame as an
author, various plots hatched by his enemies, and his stay with Hume in England (to cite just a few
examples).
137
self-proclaimed “editor” (
not
the author) of the Vicar’s sermon. In a fragment
entitled
On Proceedings against Writers
, he was the hapless victim held accountable
simply because “I put my name at the head of the book.”
445
And in dissociative
language, he argued that “one cannot… impute [the Vicar’s] sentiments to him [the
editor] unless he has expressly adopted them.”
446
This initial strategy seems facile, if
not downright specious. After all, Rousseau never refers to himself as an “editor” in
Emile
itself; all but two of his major works bore his name; and if he did not
“expressly” adopt the Vicar’s soliloquy as his own, he presents it as the thoughts of “a
man more worthy than [himself].”
447
Most significantly, however, Rousseau’s self-distancing collapses within the
Letter to Beaumont
itself, which on no uncertain terms reiterates the controversial
core of the Vicar’s creed: man’s natural innocence. As Rousseau soon points out, this
Pelagian faith unites his entire
oeuvres
:
The fundamental principle of all morality about which I have reasoned
in all my Writings and developed in this last one with all the clarity of
which I was capable, is that
man is a naturally good being
, loving
justice and order; that there is no original perversity in the human
heart, and that the first movements of nature are always right.
448
445
On Proceedings Against Writers
. CW IX.100; OC IV.1029. Readers should note that anti-papal
works were almost always published anonymously in the eighteenth century. Rousseau’s openness
both underscored his courage as an author (despite Beaumont’s charge to the contrary), and suggested
a tacit critique of
philosophes
such as Voltaire, Helvétius, and Holbach whose controversial writings
on religion never bore their names.
446
On Proceedings Against Writers
. CW IX.100; OC IV.1029.
447
Emile
. E 260.
448
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.28; OC IV.935-936. (My emphasis.) As Rousseau continues: “I have
shown that the only passion born with man, namely
amour de soi
, is a passion in itself indifferent to
good and evil; that it becomes good or bad only by accident and depending on the circumstances in
which it develops. I have shown that all the vices imputed to the human heart are not natural to it; I
have stated the manner in which they are born. I have followed their genealogy, so to speak, and I
have shown how, through continuous deterioration of their original goodness, men finally become
what they are.” This reiterates what Rousseau makes explicit in
Emile
(E 92) and the
Second
Discourse
(CW III.36-38; OC III.155-157). Note that “
amour de soi
” reflects the corrected version of
the “manifestly false” original edition which read “
amour-propre
.” OC IV.1734 (936a).
138
His courage raised, Rousseau proceeds to interrogate his Catholic rival. “You say we
are sinners because of our first father’s sin,” he continues. “But why was our first
father himself a sinner?”
449
At loss for a coherent explanation
450
he concludes that
Adam’s transgression “seems to me less a true prohibition than paternal advice. It is
a warning to abstain from a pernicious fruit that brings death.” This account is
“surely more consistent with the idea one should have of God’s goodness.”
451
Still, Rousseau is not content to merely challenge the myth of hereditary guilt.
He compounds his heresy by trivializing the gravity of Adam’s fatal choice.
There is… such a natural motive of indulgence and commiseration in
the tempter’s ruse and in the woman’s seduction
452
that, considering
Adam’s sin in all its circumstances, it can be found to be only the
slightest of faults. Yet according to them, what a fearful punishment!
It is even impossible to conceive of a more terrible one. For what
other castigation could Adam have sustained for the greatest crimes
453
449
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.30; OC IV.939.
450
This assumption is inadequate for three reasons: it follows faulty logic (“Why wouldn’t the same
reason by which you explain his sin apply to his descendants without original sin”?); disserves God (to
whom “we impute an injustice… by making ourselves sinners and punishable because of the vice of
our birth”); and rests upon a circular argument (explaining “everything except its own principle”). By
contrast, Rousseau “illumines even the fault of the first man.” But “the only thing [Beaumont] can see
is man in the hands of the Devil, while I see how he fell into them. The cause of evil, according to
you, is corrupted nature, and this corruption itself is an evil whose cause had to be sought. Man was
created good. We both agree on that, I believe. But you say he is wicked because he was wicked.
And I show how he was wicked.”
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.30-31; OC IV.939-940.
451
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.31; OC IV.940. Rousseau also makes a philological argument, noting
that “as for the menace of double death, it has been shown that this term
morte morieris
does not have
the emphasis they give it and is merely a Hebraic turn of phrase used in other places where this
emphasis cannot apply.” Theologians, in other words, are quick to distort the message of the Old
Testament. This reference is to
Genesis
2:17 (“of the tree of the knowledge of good and evil you shall
not eat, for in the day that you eat of it you shall die”). For examples of the diverse usage of
morte
morieris
see:
Genesis
20:7;
Samuel
14:44, 22:16; 2
Kings
1:4, 6, 16; and
Ezekiel
3:18, 33:8, 14.
452
This view of women as “tempters” and men as helpless victims, while not inconsistent with
Rousseau’s broader sentiment of victimization, is the understandable source of debate. For critiques of
his stance particularly as developed in
Emile
, see: Lynda Lange, “Rousseau and Modern Feminism”;
Leah Bradshaw, “Rousseau on Civic Virtue, Male Autonomy, and the Construction of the Divided
Female”; Linda Zerilli, “‘Une Maîtresse Impérieuse’: Women in Rousseau’s Semiotic Republic”; and
Rebecca Kukla, “The Coupling of Human Souls: Rousseau and the Problem of Gender Relations” in
Feminist Interpretations of Jean-Jacques Rousseau
, Lange, ed. (University Park, PA: The
Pennsylvania State University Press, 2002).
453
An earlier draft of this sentence reads: “But do you consider that the more you extenuate the fault
the more cruel you render the punishment, for what more terrible punishment could Adam have borne
139
other than being condemned to death, himself and all his race, in this
world and to spend eternity in the other one consumed by the fires of
hell? Is that the penalty imposed by the God of mercy on a poor
wretch for letting himself be fooled?
454
Adam was just a man, one “fooled” by the opposite sex. This was a vulnerability
with which Rousseau clearly identified and, as
The Confessions
detail, one to which
he frequently succumbed. To condemn Adam for falling to this temptation was to
admit his own culpability. Yet because this weakness is instinctual, it is a desire
instilled in us by God, rather than an affront to His order.
455
Guilt is instead ascribed
to those who bitterly damn man for simply adhering to his nature. “How I hate the
disheartening doctrine of our harsh Theologians,” Rousseau decries! “If I were
tempted for a moment to acknowledge it, that is when I would believe I were
blaspheming.”
456
But he did not. He insisted upon his piety, finally summoning the confidence
to defend the
Profession
directly. We learn that the Vicar’s creed is composed of two
sections. “The first part, which is the longer, the more important, the more filled with
striking and new truths, is intended to combat modern materialism, to establish the
existence of God and natural Religion with all the force of which the Author is
capable.”
457
This is the Vicar’s ode to God and rebuttal to philosophic atheism.
Although the second part, “very much shorter, less regular, and less thorough, raises
for the greatest crimes…” The phrase “could Adam have borne” replaced “could God have inflicted.”
Letter to Beaumont
(Fragment 5). CW IX.89; OC IV.1016, 1758 (1016b).
454
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.31; OC IV.940.
455
As Rousseau writes in
Emile
, “Our passions are the principal instruments of our preservation. It is,
therefore, an enterprise as vain as it is ridiculous to want to destroy them—it is to control nature, it is it
is to reform the work of God. If God were to tell men to annihilate the passions which He gives him,
God would will and not will; He would contradict himself. Never did He give this senseless order.
Nothing of the kind is written in the human heart.” E 212. Compare with E 445-446.
456
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.31; OC IV.940.
457
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.75; OC IV.996.
140
doubts and difficulties about revelations in general,” it does so purposefully “to make
each more circumspect from within his own Religion about accusing others of bad
faith within theirs, and to show that the proofs of each one are not so conclusive to all
eyes that those who do not see them with the same clarity as we do must be treated as
guilty people.”
458
The
Profession
is therefore above reproach: it pays deference to the Creator;
addresses only what is “truly essential to Religion”; arrives at these powerful truths
by confronting the Vicar’s “objections, his difficulties, his doubts”; is supported by
appeals to both conscience and reason; teaches circumspection; and uncovers
certainty only “about essential dogmas,” maintaining “a respectful skepticism about
the others.”
459
This was Rousseau’s recipe for cultivating true faith, a sentiment
nourished in the heart, not pressed upon the will or convoluted in the mind. If these
views were heretical, he maintained that they were not irreligious. Rather, he argued,
Catholic orthodoxy—not the Vicar—was guilty of disserving God.
If such ideas shocked Beaumont, Rousseau insisted that they could be found
in all his works. “I have written on various subjects, but always with the same
principles: always the same morality, the same belief, the same maxims, and if you
will the same opinions. Yet,” he laments, “contradictory judgments about my books,
or rather, about the Author of my books, have been made.”
460
Following the
First
Discourse
, he was labeled a man of paradoxes; after his
Letter on French Music
, he
became “the avowed enemy of the nation.” The
Second Discourse
changed his
reputation to that of “an atheist and a misanthrope,” the
Letter to d’Alembert
458
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.75; OC IV.996-997.
459
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.75-76; OC IV.996-997.
460
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.22; OC IV.928.
141
presented him as “the defender of Christian morality,” and
Julie
was considered
“tender and mawkish.”
461
The inconsistency of his audience is clearly a point of
contention:
the foolish public vacillates about me, knowing as little why it detests
me as why it liked me before. As for myself, I have always remained
the same: more ardent than enlightened in my quests, but sincere in
everything, even against myself; simple and good, but sensitive and
weak, often doing evil and always loving the good… demanding
nothing of men and not wishing to depend on them, yielding no more
to their prejudices than to their wills and keeping my own as free as
my reason; fearing God without being afraid of hell, reasoning about
Religion without libertinism, liking neither impiety nor fanaticism; but
hating intolerant people even more than freethinkers.
462
Here, then, is Rousseau as he sees himself: sincere in an insincere world; asking little
and giving much; a seeker of truth loathed by dogmatists and their gullible subjects;
loving God without bitterness; hating intolerance (especially when directed towards
him) and artifice. An innocent man condemned, he wanted only to reveal himself to
the public, “to hide my ways of thinking from no one, without pretense, without
artifice in all things, telling my faults to my friends, my sentiments to all the world,
and, to the public, the truths that concern it.”
463
In the end this confession reads very much like his autobiography, and
culminates in an equally confrontational conclusion. “Such are my crimes, and such
are my virtues,” Jean-Jacques declares; readers are again pressed to judge. Still, he
461
Rousseau adds: “Now [following
Emile
] I am impious. Soon perhaps I will be devout.”
Letter to
Beaumont
. CW IX.22; OC IV.928.
462
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.22; OC IV.928-929.
463
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.22; OC IV.929.
142
seemed ill-equipped to handle a negative ruling, particularly the vilification of
Emile
.
464
My
Discourse on Inequality
circulated throughout your Diocese, and
you did not write a Pastoral Letter. The
New Heloise
circulated
throughout your diocese and you did not write a Pastoral Letter. Yet
all these Books, which you have read, since you judge them, are
imbued with the same maxims. The same modes of thought are not
more disguised in them. If the subject was not suited to developing
them to the same extent… the Author’s profession of faith is found
expressed there with less reserve than that of the Savoyard Vicar.
465
This is especially true of
Julie
, whose heroine’s dying soliloquy reads like a
condensed
Profession
.
466
Yet unlike the virtuous matriarch’s fictional speech (or
even the speculative history of the
Second Discourse
), the Vicar’s sermon stands as
the moral core of a pedagogical treatise. Delivered as a lesson for its audience to
absorb by no less than a Catholic cleric, this heretical teaching was not easily
dismissed.
Although Rousseau claimed all his writings exposed “my sentiments in
matters of Religion… as they have always been in my mouth and in my heart,” he
himself felt
Emile
was different.
467
As he confessed to Beaumont, “I will always
consider [
The Profession of Faith of a Savoyard Vicar
] the best and most useful
464
At one point he insists that Beaumont was politically motivated and would not have attacked him
“if my Book had not been denounced in Parlement.”
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.26; OC IV.933.
465
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.26; OC IV.933. Rousseau repeats this claim in
The Confessions
:
“Everything that is bold in
The Social Contract
was previously in the
Discourse on Inequality
;
everything that was bold in
Emile
was previously in Julie.” CW V.342; OC I.407.
466
La Nouvelle Héloïse
appeared to applause although “the profession of faith of that very Héloïse is
exactly the same as that of the Savoyard Vicar.”
The Confessions
. OC V.342; OC I.407. Rousseau
also argued that his
Profession of Faith
was a reiteration of Julie’s dying soliloquy: “In
Emile
one finds
the profession of faith of a Catholic Priest, and in
Heloise
that of a pious woman: These two Pieces are
sufficiently in accord that one can explain one of them by the other.”
Letters Written From the
Mountain
(First Letter). CW IX.139; OC III.694. The novel itself justifies these claims. See:
Julie
,
Part VI, Letter XI, esp. pp. 584-590. See also Part VI, Letter XII on Julie’s “confession without
shame” of her love for Saint Preux. She is innocent of this indiscretion because she upheld her duty as
a wife and matriarch, even though her will could not alter her heart. CW VI.608-609; OC II.740-741.
467
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.46; OC IV.960.
143
Writing in the century during which I published it,” an estimation that “neither the
stake nor arrest warrants” might change.
468
The Vicar taught a Christian morality
essential to man’s well-being, one that emphasized our natural, divinely-scribed
potential (universally applicable to creations of the same God) rather than artificial
sectarian difference. No matter the pressure placed upon Rousseau by papists or
philosophes
, he refused to abandon this conviction. “In ordering me to be humble,
the Theologians will not make me false; and in taxing me with hypocrisy, the
philosophers will not make me profess unbelief. I shall speak of my Religion,
because I have one, and I shall speak of it loudly because I have the courage to do so
and because it would be desirable for the good of men if it were that of the human
race.”
469
Attacked by atheists and Ecclesiasts alike, Rousseau maintained a belief in his
own piety. As he pled to Beaumont, “Your Grace, I am Christian, and sincerely
Christian, according to the doctrine of the Gospel.”
470
But his faith carried a crucial
caveat: “I am Christian not as a disciple of the Priests, but as a disciple of Jesus
Christ.
471
My Master quibbled little over dogma and insisted much on duties.”
Foremost amongst these duties is brotherly love: “whoever loves God above all things
468
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.46-47; OC IV.960.
469
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.47; OC IV.960.
470
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.47; OC IV.960. Rousseau repeats and expands this claim (“I declare
myself Christian”) in
Letters Written From the Mountain
(Third Letter). CW IX.168; OC III.729.
471
By “Christian” Rousseau clearly means “Protestant” and not “Catholic.” As explained to
Beaumont, “fortunate to be born into the most reasonable and holy Religion on earth, I remain
inviolably attached to the worship of my Fathers. Like them, I take Scripture and reason for the unique
rules of my belief. Like them, I challenge the authority of men and agree to submit to their formulas
only to the extent I perceive their truth. Like them, I join in my heart with the true servants of Jesus
Christ and the true adorers of God, to offer him the homages of his Church in the communion of the
faithful.” CW IX.47; OC IV.960.
144
and his neighbor as himself is a true Christian.”
472
Because it “seems certain” that
“man is made for society, the truest Religion is also the most social and the most
humane.”
473
Still, Rousseau admitted that empirical evidence hardly confirmed his
conclusion. His peculiar faith was “subject to great difficulties from the historical
account and the facts that contradict it.” Despite insisting that religion benefited
society, Jews (they “began their establishment by destroying seven nations”),
Christians (“all… have had wars of Religion”), and the celibate demonstrated that
religious practice often disserves man’s best interests.
474
Rather than discourage him, this harsh reality only affirmed his belief in the
value of the Vicar’s sermon. To bridge the gap between how things are and how they
should be, we must maintain faith in man’s innocence despite overwhelming evidence
to the contrary. The Vicar provides such hope amidst despair because, like God
Himself, he speaks directly to the heart independently of both mind and will.
475
Unlike papal dogma, he convinces without coercion. And unlike atheism, he raises
doubts, dissentions, and objections to human religion without abandoning God. This
is why “every man who believes in God, of whatever religion he might be, will never
read the profession of the Savoyard vicar without being moved by it.”
476
No matter
what others claimed, this creed offered a genuinely beneficial faith to denatured
individuals desperately in need of guidance from their benevolent, omnipotent
Creator.
472
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.47; OC IV.960. Citing Matthew 7:12 and Galatians 5:14, Rousseau
reminds us that when Christ “summed up the Law and the Prophets, it was more in acts of virtue than
in formulas of belief, and he told me himself and through his Apostles that the person who loves his
brother has fulfilled the Law.”
473
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.54; OC IV.969.
474
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.54-55; OC IV.970.
475
Julie
. CW VI.609; OC II.741.
476
Letter to Beaumont
(Fragment 14). CW IX.98; OC IV.1026.
145
* * * * *
The Vicar’s profession ends as it began, with a declaration of love of the truth.
Its pursuit is our principal duty on earth, he concludes, one to uphold no matter the
costs. “Whether they love you or hate you, whether they read or despise your
writings, it does not matter; speak the truth; do the good.”
477
Taking this love “as my
whole philosophy,” he wonders where is “the philosopher who would not gladly
deceive mankind for his own glory? Where is the one who in the secrecy of his heart
sets himself any other goal than that of distinguishing himself?”
478
By his own
account, Rousseau himself. In adopting Juvenal’s lines as his motto, he had dedicated
his life to this very aim.
479
Less well known is an earlier maxim that graced only two of his published
writings. Taken from Ovid’s
Tristia
, it first appears in the closing of a January 17,
1742 correspondence to François-Joseph de Conzié: “Here it is that I am a barbarian,
understood by nobody.”
480
In this letter the quote is used quite literally: Jean-Jacques
hopes the
comte
will “take his frankness in the meaning in which it is offered,” not to
offend but as the honest testimony of an oft-misread man “who speaks from
477
Emile
. E 313.
478
Emile
. E 269.
479
See: Juvenal,
The Satires
, IV.89-91. Rousseau mentions this motto in
Emile
(E 206),
Letter to
d’Alembert
, the epigraph to
Letters Written From the Mountain
, and
The Reveries of the Solitary
Walker
(Fourth Promenade).
480
Rousseau à François-Joseph de Conzié
,
comte des Charmettes
, January 17, 1742. CC I.43.139.
Translation from
Tristia
V.x.36 taken from Ovid,
Volume VI
, Arthur Leslie Wheeler, tr. (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1988), p. 249. In the letter, Rousseau adds line 37 (“the Gatae laugh
stupidly at Latin words”) which does not appear in the dedicatory epistles to the
First Discourse
and
Dialogues
.
146
experience.”
481
As with falsely impugned guilt Rousseau abhorred misunderstanding,
particularly of his forthright
oeuvre
. Expecting that his age would identify within
them “the heart of a good man,” he encountered only scorn. “The people hate me, I
know it, but that is not their fault; this hatred is again the work of its tyrants; it is not
me that it hates, it is what it has been told I was.”
482
Rousseau’s paranoia is, however, misleading. The people did
not
hate him: he
was acclaimed throughout Europe,
Julie
was the century’s bestselling novel, and he
received an inordinate amount of fan mail from readers who felt personally touched
by his passionate works.
483
Even more striking than the inaccuracy of Rousseau’s
assessment is the helplessness he attributes to his peers. They are easily manipulated
by “tyrants,” cruel, “self-interested and jealous men” like the papists, philosophers
and Parlement officials who used pastoral letters, stakes and warrants to “disturb and
deceive.” Even as he trusted
les peuples
to read his heart, he seemed convinced of
their incapacity to do so. Yet like himself they were innocent victims subject to the
wicked machinations of forces beyond their control, and therefore not to blame.
Awash in discouragement, Rousseau looked for redemption in a possible
future.
484
One day his enemies’ “outcries will finally end and my writings will
481
CC I.43.139. When Ovid’s quote appears again (as the dedicatory epistle of the
First Discourse
), it
raises a striking paradox: Rousseau initiated his literary career by attacking the arts, and used as his
dedication the words of a misunderstood poet. Puffendorf also quotes the same verse in his
Right of
Nature and of Nations
(IV.I.vi) when discussing the origin of languages.
482
Letter to Beaumont
(Fragment 12). CW IX.94; OC IV.1021-1022.
483
See: Darnton, “Readers Respond to Rousseau: The Fabrication of Romantic Sensitivity”;
The
Forbidden Best-Sellers of Pre-Revolutionary France
.
484
“One day perhaps what is the shame of my century will be its glory, and those who will read my
book [
Emile
] will say with admiration: How angelic those times must have been in which a book like
that was regarded as impious, doubtless then all writings breathed the most sublime devoutness and the
earth was covered with nothing but saints.”
Letter to Beaumont
(Fragment 14). CW IX.98; OC
IV.1026. Dripping with sarcasm, this claim prepares us for the opening to
The Confessions
in which
Rousseau suggests to his audience that they were certainly no better than he. Note that in the final
147
remain to [their] shame.” Only then would he be avenged by “less prejudiced
Christians” who might recognize the concord, charity, and “morality of their divine
master” imbued in his ideas.
485
In so casting his gaze, Rousseau looked as he often
did, in different directions—towards a better future while dwelling on a disappointing
past. Possible redemption offered some solace, and he was willing to sacrifice his
present happiness to serve a higher good.
486
This sense of martyrdom placed him in
the shadows of Jesus and Socrates. “They crucified my master and gave hemlock to a
man who was worth more than I,” Rousseau confides.
487
If he was not their equal he
nonetheless felt their burden. Preaching truths to a vengeful, intolerant society, he
assumed history would treat his paradoxes as kindly as it did those of his forebears.
Only then would “the glory to which I laid claim” be recognized.
488
If such faith seems irreconcilable with his acute doubt, we must remember
that Rousseau never conflated natural goodness with incorruptibility. Far from it, the
Vicar notes, “the fact that I act in good faith does not mean I believe myself
infallible.”
489
Nor did Jean-Jacques. As his own testimony proves, he was a man of
many flaws, one who (despite insistence otherwise) occasionally acted in bad faith.
He simply did not take his errancy as proof of irredeemable guilt. Rather, to
printed version, he removes an explicit mention of the Vicar’s faith. Compare with:
Letter to
Beaumont
. CW IX.60; OC IV.984-985.
485
Letter to Beaumont
(Fragment 12). CW IX.94; OC IV.1021.
486
“I said to myself, oh what good would be done for men by the one who would tell them the truth
without disguise, without fear, without satire and without flattery, the one who, uprooting their base
prejudices, would dry up the source of their miseries, the one who would make them see that they are
wicked only because they are dupes, and unhappy only because they are foolish, the one who would
teach them that they are made to be happy and good and what they have to do to be so… I have tried to
be that man; at least I dared to be him, and what is most difficult in this enterprise is courage.”
Letter
to Beaumont
(Fragment 10). CW IX.91-92; OC IV.1018-1019.
487
Letter to Beaumont
(Fragment 5). CW IX.89; OC IV.1016.
488
Rousseau describes this “glory” as “a sincere desire to be useful and true, disinterestedness, and
good faith.” His faith is evidenced by both his dedication to public welfare and his non-partisanship.
Letter to Beaumont
(Fragment 10). CW IX.92; OC IV.1019.
489
Emile
. E 294.
148
Rousseau and society alike, lapses merely reiterated the need for positive guidance.
“As I justly distrust myself,” the Vicar divulges, “the only thing that I ask of [God],
or rather that I expect of His justice, is to correct my error if I am led astray and if this
error is dangerous to me.” Yet if the strength to stay a steady course fails, “of what
can I be guilty? It is up to the truth to come nearer.”
490
This, finally, was Rousseau’s objective: to bring the truth nearer. This is what
drove him to explain how we had fallen from our natural state; how everything
degenerates in human hands; why man was/is
491
born free, yet everywhere in chains;
why divine guidance was both accessible and necessary; where society erred, and
how individuals might still be redeemed by rekindling the divine sentiment within us.
Yet how can we be both free and in chains? Inherently good and authors of sin?
Deeply innocent yet demonstrably guilty? Ruled by dogmatists if God’s order is so
evident and compelling? Paradoxes such as these have beguiled readers for more
than two hundred years; are they only now resolvable, much less pardonable?
If we approach Rousseau’s paradoxes not as contradictions demanding
definitive resolutions, but as antinomies intrinsic to the human condition, they might
yet serve a practical purpose: stoking our courage and desire to change a world itself
characterized by vicious contradictions, without letting us lapse into cynical apathy.
After all, Rousseau himself believed that his combined expression of acute discomfort
and unbounded faith was a necessary catalyst for reform. Still, we need not rush to
judgment. Before assessing the coherence and practical utility of his dissonant vision,
490
Emile
. E 294.
491
The original sentence—“L’homme est né libre, et partout il est dans les fers”—is ambiguous. In
French, it can refer to both a past and present condition: man either “was” or “is” born free.
The Social
Contract
. OC III.351. For a discussion of the implications of each translation see CW IV.xiii.
149
we might first turn to another theme that illustrates the confluence of religious and
secular traditions so crucial to his work: reclusiveness.
150
Chapter 4: The Reluctant Recluse
A truly happy being is a solitary being. God alone enjoys an absolute happiness. But
who among us has the idea of it?
—Rousseau,
Emile
492
Il n' y a que le méchant qui soit seul.
—Diderot,
Le fils naturel
, Act IV, Scene III.
493
As with innocence, reclusiveness is a theme prominent within Rousseau’s life
and works, and one that illustrates his peculiar incorporation of Christian and Pagan
traditions.
494
In praising solitude, Rousseau (in)famously distanced himself from his
peers, stressing his uniqueness while levying stark critiques upon the society of his
contemporaries’ making. He championed the virtues of Geneva as an expatriate in
France, and waxed eloquent on mankind’s natural state of ignorant, innocent
isolation. What began as a largely theoretical enterprise—a public figure’s praise of
isolation and withdrawal—took a highly politicized turn towards the literal.
Following the publication of his most controversial work—
Emile
, and its chapter
The
Profession of Faith of a Savoyard Vicar
—Rousseau was exiled, forced into the very
seclusion he had for so long argued was an antidote to corrupting social relations.
492
Emile
. E 221.
493
“Only the wicked are alone.” Diderot,
Œuvres
,
Tome IV
, p. 1113.
494
The etymology of the word “recluse” confirms its religious overtones. According to the
Oxford
English Dictionary
, “recluse” refers to persons “secluded from society, especially as a religious
discipline.” A recluses can describe either “[a] person shut up from the world for the purpose of
religious meditation” (such as monks or hermits), or someone “who lives a retired life, one who mixes
little with society.”
151
If Rousseau is far more religious than is commonly held, his religiosity is
nonetheless qualified by a concurrent commitment to temporal aims and secular
values. This phenomenon is particularly evident in his appropriation of Christian and
Pagan models of withdrawal. To support this claim, I will examine Rousseau’s
evolution as a recluse from the demonstrative self-distancing of his early career, to a
more mature incorporation of isolation into a model of civic education, to his final,
literal retreat from Montmorency following the censure of
Emile
and
The Social
Contract
.
Despite its many guises, the theme of reclusiveness remained central to
Rousseau’s thought. He was, in practice if not by design,
495
a consummate outsider.
This applies in three senses of the word. First,
figuratively
, as “[o]ne who is outside
any enclosure, barrier, or boundary.”
496
Second,
practically
, as “[a] person who is
isolated from or does not ‘fit’ into conventional society either through choice or on
account of some social, intellectual, etc., reason.”
497
And third,
literally
, as “[o]ne
whose position is on the outside of some group or series,” “a non-member.”
498
Throughout his works, Rousseau reminds us that he was “not made like any
[other] that exist.”
499
A “natural” individual in a denatured society, an honest author
at odds with his vain philosophical peers, and a truly pious believer deeply critical of
495
The self-consciousness with which Rousseau pursued his highly unfashionable claim to the truth
supports the argument that his solitude was in fact calculated from the outset. Numerous examples in
his early writings stress the fact that he understood and accepted the alienating consequences of his
political philosophy. At the same time, Rousseau can be read as a highly unaccountable author, a
phenomenon discussed at great length by Jean Starobinski as evidence of his passivity and propensity
towards personal deflection. In this sense, Rousseau’s solitude may be read as the consequence of
forces beyond his control, a description particularly suited to his discussion of his flight from
Montmorency in
The Confessions
.
496
The Oxford English Dictionary
, Sense 1A.
497
Ibid., Sense 1C.
498
Ibid., Sense 2 and 1A.
499
The Confessions
. CW V.5; OC I.5.
152
the Catholic church, these distinctions established his unabashed uniqueness. He was
also a man of unbounded temperament: the force of his writings, the frequency of his
fractured relationships, and his willingness to adopt unfashionable stances—to attack,
for example, both atheists and papists alike—testify to this fierce independence.
Rousseau’s resistance to assimilate was the result of choices made, but ones
over which he professes to have had very little control.
500
The reasons were in part
social. He was born to a petty
bourgeois
family and identified himself with the
common man; he abhorred the vacuous privileges of the upper class and the hierarchy
of European social castes; he abandoned fashionable garb for Cossack robes, and
stressed his inability to master social conventions;
501
and he repeatedly subverted any
chances he had in securing a life of upward mobility.
502
In defying convention,
Rousseau challenged boundaries both formally and substantively, using opera, novels,
letters, plays, prose and dialogues as vehicles for his sharp social commentary.
The Genevan was particularly an outsider in his religious thought. Convinced
of his piety yet charged with heresy, he condemned Church and academy alike for
furthering their own particular aims at the expense of the general good. Catholic
500
Starobinski interprets Rousseau’s passivity as a justification for his lack of control. As he writes in
Transparency and Obstruction
, “Rousseau almost always prefers to avoid action and effort.” See:
Transparency and Obstruction
, p. 91.
501
Rousseau also claimed to have practical reasons for wearing robes: they purportedly alleviated the
pains of his well-publicized urinary tract disorder.
502
To this point, consider Rousseau’s following recollection: “I renounced forever every project of
fortune and advancement. Determined to pass the little time I had left to live in independence and
poverty, I applied all the strength of my soul to breaking the irons of opinion, and to doing
courageously everything that appeared good to me, without bothering myself in any way about the
judgment of men.”
The Confessions
. CW V.303-304; OC I.362. Rousseau offers numerous additional
examples, including his frequent (and abrupt) career changes, his failure to meet the King of France
one day after
Le Devin du Village
premiered, and his dispute with Hume and subsequent rejection of
King George III’s offer of an annual pension.
153
leaders labeled him a dangerous heretic,
503
while his attack on the arts and sciences
prompted Voltaire to wonder, “What about Jean-Jacques’ book against the theater?
Has he become a priest of the Church?”
504
It is no mean feat to simultaneously
alienate atheists and papists; but for Rousseau,
solitaire extraordinaire
, such
estrangement exemplifies the isolating effects of his thought.
Taken within the context of his broader political project, we may understand
Rousseau’s aggressive self-distancing as the means to a coherent end: society’s
redemption, an aspiration at times facilitated by active withdrawal. Yet even if we
allow him the consistency he claimed was a hallmark of his entire
oeuvres
,
505
how
might we make sense of the apparent contradictions at play? An outsider so deeply
involved with the in-crowd, so insistently proud of a nation to which he never
returned (and eventually renounced),
506
so scornful of the public eye his writings
resoundingly drew, Rousseau was a man of conundrums if not outright
contradictions.
A natural individual caught in the perverse machinations of a denatured world,
he sought recourse in solitude. But what, specifically, did his praise of withdrawal
suggest? Was it the wicked rumination of a misguided misanthrope, as Diderot
implied? The embrace of a ‘horrible’ life opposed to society, as described in the
503
The Archbishop Christophe de Beaumont condemned
Emile
(and, by implication, its author) as
“containing an abominable doctrine, suited to overturning natural Law and to destroying the
foundations of the Christian Religion… tending to disturb the peace of States, to stir up Subjects
against the authority of their Sovereign,” in short, a “scandalous” work, “erroneous, impious,
blasphemous, and heretical.”
Pastoral Letter of his Grace the Archbishop of Paris
. CW IX.16.
504
Besterman XIX.D7864. See also: Cranston,
The Noble Savage
, p. 137.
505
Rousseau begins his religious self-defense in the
Letter to Beaumont
by stressing his consistency: “I
have written on various subjects, but always with the same maxims, and if you will the same
opinions.” This is an oft-repeated claim of Rousseau’s, specifically evoked to defend himself from the
increasing controversy his works generated. See:
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.22; OC IV.928.
506
Rousseau renounced his Genevan citizenship on May 12, 1763.
154
Encyclopédie
?
507
The retreat of a religious individual unconcerned with earthly
affairs? Or the compelling reaction of a good man caught in a less-than-virtuous
society?
508
What forms did it take, and what does this reveal about the broader
tension in his works between spiritual and secular salvation, heuristic idealism and
pessimistic realism? How does a study of this theme illuminate our understanding of
Rousseau generally, and his secular appropriation of Christian themes specifically? Is
his model of reclusiveness compatible with his dream of democratic virtue, or does it
merely punctuate the incoherence of his enterprise?
The road to these answers winds through three stages and three different
senses of retreat. Before treading down this path, let us begin from the beginning, not
of Jean-Jacques’ life, but of his career.
* * * * *
Rousseau was a recluse. To anyone familiar with the author, this point should
hardly seem contentious. According to his
Confessions
, even the most perfunctory of
social obligations left him deeply disconcerted.
509
A sensitive soul whose life’s work
507
In his entry, Jaucourt condemns solitude as an
horreur
(even, notably, for the Christian) and “[un]
état opposé à celui de la société.” The solitary man is no less spared: “Cet état est celui où l'on conçoit
que se trouveroit l'homme s'il vivoit absolument seul abandonné à lui-même, & destitué de tout
commerce avec ses semblables. Un tel homme seroit sans doute bien misérable, & se trouveroit sans
cesse exposé par sa foiblesse & son ignorance à périr de faim, de froid, ou par les dents de quelque
bête féroce. L'état de société pourvoit à ses besoins, & lui procure la sûreté, la nourriture & les
douceurs de la vie.” Diderot,
Encyclopédie
, Tome XV, p. 325.
508
In his introduction to the English translation of
The Confessions
, Christopher Kelly distinguishes
between “goodness” and “virtue” in Rousseau’s works: “Goodness allows one to follow one’s
inclinations without (usually) harming anyone else. Virtue allows one to overcome one’s inclinations
on those occasions when they would lead to harming someone else. While goodness is a natural
quality, virtue is a moral quality made necessary by the complexity of social life.” This distinction
helps reconcile the tension posed by Rousseau’s formulation that man is naturally good although
society lacks virtue. For Kelly’s full discussion see: CW V.xxiii-xxiv.
509
According to Rousseau, his social skills were subverted by “slowness in thinking joined with…
liveliness in feeling,” a condition that afflicted him both alone and in company. “So little master of my
155
thrust him into the public spotlight, the added attention caused him significant woe.
In the 1763 preface to his
First Discourse
, Rousseau disparaged his “celebrity” as “an
abyss of miseries.”
510
Truth be told, not everyone has the stomach for such a life (as
his remorse makes painfully clear). But Rousseau’s “miseries” reflect much deeper
concerns. By the
Second Discourse
we learn that social attachments opened
Pandora’s box. Mankind—innocent, ignorant and content in the state of nature—was
corrupted, subjugated by the inegalitarian relations borne of civil society.
Rousseau—innocent,
511
learned, profoundly malcontent—took this perverse
development to heart.
His critique of inequality took sweeping aim at social relations, and drew
resounding protest from those threatened by his assessments of private property and
contemporary society alike. Yet he continued to speak his mind, no matter the
consequences. Rousseau was well aware of the alienating effect his ideas had; the
enmity of his contemporaries was simply not enough to deter him. “I foresee that I
will not easily be forgiven for the side I have dared to take,” he admits. “Running
counter to everything that men admire today, I can expect only universal blame.”
512
But unlike Crispus, who appeased the tyrant Domitian with tactful silence, Rousseau
vowed to do what the Roman courtesan had not: “freely state his opinions and risk his
mind when I am all by myself, one can judge what I must be in conversation, where, in order to speak
to the point one must think about a thousand things simultaneously and on the spot. The mere idea of
so many social conventions, at least one of which I am certain to forget, is enough to intimidate me. I
do not understand how one even dares to speak in a social circle.”
The Confessions
. CW V.95-96; OC
I.113-115.
510
This comes from a Forward to the revised Preface, written approximately thirteen years after the
First Discourse
was first published.
First Discourse
(1763 Forward). CW II.3; OC I.1237.
511
I am referring to Rousseau’s triple claim of innocence:
natural
(the Pelagian heresy at the heart of
the
Profession of Faith of a Savoyard Vicar
);
juridical
(in the charges levied against
Emile
and
The
Social Contract
); and
personal
(an individual who is good of heart and attuned to his natural
innocence).
512
1763 Preface to the
First Discourse
. CW II.3; OC III.3.
156
life for the truth.”
513
Taking these words as his motto, Rousseau drew a line between
himself and his entire age, particularly “the Witty or the Fashionable”
514
philosophes
who wrote with smug self-satisfaction, and papists whose dogmatism dictated the
terms of individual material worship.
Rousseau was no stranger to contrariness. Yet in typically paradoxical
fashion, he decried its frequency amongst philosophers as a form of sophistry, a vain
method of self-promotion used to garner recognition. Academics favored personal
accolades above the public good, and cherished individual success more than genuine
virtue. As Rousseau clarified in his 1753
Preface to Narcisse
, the “taste for letters…
is born from the desire to distinguish oneself.”
515
This desire “necessarily produces
ills that are infinitely more dangerous than all the good that they do is useful,” and
“makes those who surrender to it very unscrupulous about means for succeeding.”
516
The philosopher’s quest is painted in terms reminiscent of the Bible’s Edenic lesson:
the fruits of knowledge may be tempting, but their acquisition precipitates a morally
crippling sacrifice. In the zeal to acquire individual enlightenment, to distinguish
themselves from their peers, philosophers succumb to self-interest while shirking
their duties as citizens.
Although Rousseau does not categorically dismiss philosophical speculation,
he wags a stiff finger at those who pursue wisdom under false pretenses and seek
recognition at any cost. In one frenzied stroke, and along these lines, he castigates
513
Juvenal,
The Satires
, p. 28.
514
Rousseau strikes a grandiose concern for posterity: “One must not write for such Readers when one
wants to live beyond one’s century.” 1763 Preface to the
First Discourse
. CW II.3; OC III.3.
515
Preface to Narcisse
. CW II.191; OC II.965.
516
Preface to Narcisse
. CW II.191; OC II.965.
157
two thousand years of Western political thought from ancient Greece to the Middle
Ages:
The first Philosophers made a great reputation for themselves by
teaching men the practice of their duties and the principles of virtue.
But soon these precepts having become common, it was necessary to
distinguish oneself by opening up contrary routes. Such is the origin
of the absurd systems of Leucippus, Diogenes, Pyrrho, Protagoras,
Lucretius. Hobbes, Mandeville and a thousand others have pretended
to distinguish themselves among us; and their dangerous doctrine has
borne such fruit, that although we still have some Philosophers ardent
to recall the laws of humanity and virtue to our hearts, one is surprised
to see to what point our reasoning century has pushed disdain for the
duties of man and of citizen to its maxims.
517
Those who seek “to recall the laws of humanity and virtue to our hearts” form a
lonely minority. Most philosophers are, by contrast, charged with grave negligence,
vain ambition, and the correlative “fruit” of self-glorification. In attempting to further
their reputations, they privilege spectacle above substance or utility. And from a
moral standpoint, they neglect their most truly noble service: namely, the “duties of
man and of citizen,” subsumed under the satiation of self-interest. As Rousseau
elaborates, “[t]he taste for letters, philosophy and the fine arts destroys love of our
primary duties and of genuine glory. Once talents have seized the honors due to
virtue, everyone wishes to be an agreeable man and no one concerns himself with
being a good man.”
518
The harsh certainty of Jean-Jacques’ judgment soon proved ironic. Two years
later, fellow Genevan Charles Bonnet levied precisely the same charge against
hi
,
attacking the
Second Discourse
as the paradoxical work of a self-promoting rabble-
517
Preface to Narcisse
. CW II.191; OC II.965-966.
518
Preface to Narcisse
. CW II.191; OC II.966.
158
rouser.
519
This followed Diderot’s claim (echoed by Voltaire) that the
First
Discourse
represented a deliberate change of heart, a position on the arts and sciences
calculated to garner its author attention and notoriety. Infuriated by the insinuation,
Rousseau rose to his own defense.
520
Certain that his work served society’s best
interests, he defended himself by stressing his own uniqueness. Unlike his more
decorated peers, he was both capable of recognizing the “absurdity” of their maxims,
and bold enough to challenge them.
521
The singularity of his vision was matched
only by his dedication to revealing the truth, qualities that distinguished him as a
champion of society’s salvation.
522
It was this unique combination of clarity and
courage in the face of overwhelming pressure that set him apart. Far from serving his
own self-interest, Rousseau was the sole author of his age who dared to challenge the
mighty empires of both
philosophe
and Papal dogma.
523
Compelled to respond against the very charges he had levied upon
philosophers in his
First Discourse
, Rousseau’s defense came at a price: it further
isolated him. Having taken society to task, he was forced to emphasize his role as a
recluse amongst philosophers, the sole intellectual who stood apart—and alone—on
519
See:
Letter from M. Philopolis
. CW III.123-126; OC III.1383-1386.
520
Although James Miller downplays Rousseau’s efforts to rebuke Voltaire’s barbs, Rousseau’s
correspondence suggests that he responded passionately on numerous occasions. See
Rousseau:
Dreamer of Democracy
, p. 53.
521
As Rousseau replies, “Let us suppose that a singular mind (
esprit
), bizarre, and in fact a man of
paradoxes, then dared to reproach others for the absurdity of their maxims, to prove to them that they
run to death in seeking tranquility, that by dint of being reasonable they do nothing but ramble.”
Letter
from J.-J. Rousseau to M. Philopolis
. OC.III.231; CW III.127. It is also worth noting that Bonnet’s
pseudonym, “Mr. City-lover,” was certainly conceived in antagonism towards Rousseau.
522
Rousseau’s sense of his own uniqueness is, in this respect, greatly exaggerated. There were, of
course, dozens of other entries for the prize of Dijon that likewise attacked the arts and sciences as a
corrupt influence upon society. For a further discussion of this theme see: P-M Masson,
La religion de
Jean-Jacques Rousseau
, Vol. I, pp. 259-261.
523
For Rousseau, Church and academy were birds of a feather: “The two parties attack each other
reciprocally with so many sophisms,” yet neither fosters virtue, goodness or meaningful
enlightenment
Emile
. E 312n.
159
behalf of all. The condemnation he had foreseen as a consequence of his contrariness
was materializing. In claiming his innocence, he merely drove a deeper wedge
between himself and his culpable age. Attacking ideas and occupations his powerful
counterparts held dear, he was forced to retreat from their ranks. His praise of
solitude, coupled with a condemnation of society, placed him in a lonely corner
indeed.
A philosopher who attacked philosophers, a storied member of the
Enlightenment who was also one of its most vociferous critics,
524
Rousseau pulled
few punches. If vainglory was a capital offense, masquerading private interests as
public goods was a cardinal sin. Philosophers, that “troop of charlatans, each crying
from his own spot on a public square: Come to me, I alone do not deceive,” were
doubly guilty.
525
Like Christian clerics, they presented their ideas as gospel, coercing
men to bow under the authority of their vacuous reasoning. “Under the haughty
pretext that they alone are enlightened, true, and of good faith,” Rousseau’s Vicar
chides, “they imperiously subject us to their peremptory decisions and claim to give
us as the true principles of things the unintelligible systems they have built in their
imagination.”
526
Like Catholic clerics, philosophers abuse the privileges of their self-
anointed grace, parading elaborate, incoherent opinion as irrefutable truth. And in so
doing, they demand subservience to hollow ideals unfulfilled in practice, a
524
Darrin M. McMahon describes Rousseau’s influence on anti-
philosophes
who “borrowed from him
extensively, citing Rousseau’s passages against their common enemies; sharing his dissatisfaction with
the corruption of the age; and echoing his belief that sentiment, emotion, and feeling were wellsprings
of faith.” See: McMahon,
Enemies of the Enlightenment: The French Counter-Enlightenment and the
Making of Modernity
. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), p. 35.
525
First Discourse
. CW II.20; OC III.27.
526
Emile
. E 312.
160
phenomenon exemplifying society’s most perverse pressure: the denaturing rule of
doxa
.
By contrast, Rousseau presented himself to the public as a good, honest soul
attuned to their best interests. Yet he challenged the motives of philosophers while
producing an enormous body of philosophical literature; he attacked their ersatz
claims to supposed truths while dedicating his life to that very pursuit. What, then,
made Rousseau any different? Why were his works alone free of the self-interested
sophistry so rampant amongst his much-maligned peers?
For one, Jean-Jacques took shelter in his self-proclaimed commonness. In the
penultimate paragraph of his
First Discourse
, he addressed average readers as one of
their ranks: “As for us, common men not endowed by Heaven with such great talents
and not destined for so much glory, let us remain in our obscurity. Let us not chase
after a reputation which would escape us, and which in the present state of things
would never be worth what it cost, even if we had all the qualifications to obtain
it.”
527
Rousseau was not entirely without cause in siding with the common man.
After all, his origins were humble: the son of a Genevan watch-maker, a largely self-
taught runaway who toiled through various ignoble positions on a circuitous and
surprising path to fame. Yet what most set Rousseau apart from his fellow
philosophes
was the very insistence with which he set himself apart. He cultivated
his commonness as an antidote to their erudition,
528
stressing his solidarity with a
527
First Discourse
. CW II.22; OC III.30. It is worth noting the language of Rousseau’s phrase: “As
for us, common men…” Bear in mind that this essay was written for the Academy at Dijon—and
certainly
not
the so-called “
hommes vulgaires
” with whom Rousseau identifies and purportedly
addresses.
528
Despite Rousseau’s charge, he was a notably erudite and voraciously self-educated figure. What
separates him from other “philosophers” was not his degree of learnedness, but rather his application
of scholarly knowledge to practical problems such as civic duty and religious reform.
161
general populace endowed with neither the means nor the motive to distinguish
themselves. Insistent upon his uniqueness, Rousseau took refuge in his affinity for
the average.
At this beginning stage in his career, he had not yet achieved the fame and
recognition that he would almost immediately rue. As such, it would be premature to
simply dismiss him as a blind hypocrite. Yet the very fact that his career in letters
began with a renunciation of a career in letters, that his arrival into the
philosophe
circle was coupled with a hyperbolic criticism of philosophy, that he established his
uniqueness by praising his commonness, attests to a curious methodology. Had
Rousseau been a recluse in the strictest sense of the word, he would have kept quiet
(or, at the very least, less visible). Instead, he raised his voice to a fevered pitch and
in so doing invited scrutiny upon himself. Why would someone so philosophically
gifted subvert the very enterprise he had chosen to undertake? Why would an author
of operas and plays criticize the arts and sciences? Why would Rousseau attack
contrariness and self-promotion while trumpeting his own honesty, utility and
forthrightness in decidedly contrary prose?
His simultaneous isolation and involvement sounded the demonstrative outcry
of a social reformer. If Rousseau was sincere in his praise of solitude, so was he
equally concerned with civic welfare: the society in which he felt entirely ill at ease
was desperately in need of salvation. Although his acute discomfort certainly
informed his recourse to retreat, in taking seriously his duty as a citizen he could not
in good faith (nor in good conscience) abandon his fellow men. For the Rousseau of
162
these early years, his reclusiveness was
necessarily
demonstrative: he was far too
concerned to completely absolve himself, and far to critical to assimilate.
Alone amongst philosophers, his solitary role as champion of
les peuples
served a distinct pedagogical purpose: to demonstrate the folly of his hubristic peers
while reminding us of the true path to a more natural, virtuous existence. As he
rhapsodizes in the
First Discourse
’s final paragraph, “O virtue! Sublime science of
simple souls, are so many difficulties and preparations needed to know you? Are not
your principles engraved in all hearts, and is it not enough in order to learn your Laws
to return into oneself and listen to the voice of one’s conscience in the silence of the
passions?”
529
The retreat is three-fold. In claiming that true virtue—that “sublime
science”—is engraved in our hearts and revealed through conscience, Rousseau
discredits and distances himself from the mediating roles of Church and academy,
withdraws into the company of the indeterminate and anonymous everyman, and
retreats into the depths of his heart (with divinely-crafted conscience as guide) to
recapture his innate moral sensibility.
The proposal is radical. Retreat—from vain ambition, from the path to
academic success, from the “vanity and emptiness of those proud titles that dazzle
us,”
530
from the seductions of sophistic logic, from self-serving erudition—is nothing
short of necessary. If virtue is inscribed on our very hearts (works of God’s
authorship), its acquisition calls for little more than looking inwards, withdrawing
from a perverse society to retrieve our natural goodness.
529
First Discourse
. CW II.22; OC III.30.
530
First Discourse
. CW II.12; OC III.16.
163
The Pelagian overtones are explicit. Despite his earlier description of
philosophical wisdom as a dangerous “fruit,” any mention of Adam’s debilitating
legacy is conspicuously absent in Rousseau’s praise of human nature. Instead, he
argues, we must place faith in our innate goodness. Foreshadowing his later, more
explicit denial of Original Sin in
Emile
,
531
Rousseau insists from the outset that
society—not man as God’s creation—is to blame. Natural man is above reproach,
but socialized men are prone to wickedness. Rousseau’s unerring faith in natural
goodness is nonetheless problematized by his polemics. There appears to be a
discrepancy between his ontology and his empiricism, between his description of
human nature and his observations of human society: if
man
is good, how can
men
be
so wicked?
532
The
Second Discourse
clarified this dilemma, presenting a concise genealogy
of humankind’s fall from grace. In our natural state we are innocent and ignorant,
pre-moral creatures bound only by
amour-de-soi
and
pitié
, sentiments that
encouraged self-preservation and mutual sympathy. It was not until the emergence of
civil society—a revolution following the advent of private property—that natural
531
The
Profession of Faith of the Savoyard Vicar
spawned the Pelagian controversy central to
Emile
’s
censure. In defense, Rousseau reiterated the consistency of his works, city his
Second Discourse
,
Letter to d’Alembert
, and
Julie
as being “imbued with the same maxims. The same modes of thought
are not more disguised in them… and the Author’s profession of faith is found expressed there with
less reserve than that of the Savoyard Vicar.”
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.26; OC IV.933. Compare
this with the following statement from
The Confessions
: “I dare to say… what seems almost
unbelievable, the profession of faith of that very Héloïse dying is exactly the same as that of the
Savoyard Vicar. Everything that is bold in
The Social Contract
was previously in the
Discourse on
Inequality
; everything that was bold in
Emile
was previously in
Julie
. Now these bold things excited
no clamor against the two former works; thus they were not the things that excited it against the latter.”
CW V.342; OC I.407.
532
Rousseau stands by this logic in his
Letter to Beaumont
: “If man is good by his nature, as I believe I
have demonstrated, it follows that he remains so as long as nothing foreign to himself spoils him. And
if men are wicked, as they have gone to the trouble of teaching me, it follows that their wickedness
comes from somewhere else.” CW IX.35; OC IV.945. For an extended discussion of this tension,
refer to note 18 (above).
164
inequalities fostered social inequalities, that vicious divisions were introduced and
reified by social institutions privileging the interests of few above the welfare of
all.
533
Although Voltaire famously chided that Rousseau would send us back to the
woods crawling on all fours,
534
the latter makes plain that humankind cannot retreat to
a state of nature. Rousseau adamantly maintained that “such a return would be a
miracle both so great and so harmful that only God could do it and only the Devil
could wish it.”
535
Society is, for better or (more often) worse, a necessary facet of
human life. In later works such as
The Social Contract
, and writings on Poland,
Corsica and Geneva, Rousseau presented concrete models of political reform,
envisioning virtuous societies conducive to legitimized self-rule. Yet at this early
stage, his prescriptive optimism was overshadowed by his brash skepticism.
Although firm in his belief that human existence was inextricably tied to society,
Jean-Jacques’ deep discomfort implied that if we could not return to nature, we might
do well to withdraw.
Strong words notwithstanding, Rousseau removed himself in spirit more than
flesh. His initial period of withdrawal took the form of contrariness, vocal retaliation
against his illustrious peers and soon-to-be former friends. If anything, his
533
For Rousseau’s full account see:
Second Discourse
. CW III.43-55; OC III.164-179. He describes
the “invention” of private property as a deceptively simple ruse: “The first person who, having fenced
off a plot of ground, took it into his head to say
this is mine
and found people simple enough to believe
him.”
Second Discourse
. CW III.43; OC III.164.
534
As Voltaire quipped, “[o]ne acquires the desire to walk on all fours when one reads your work.”
Letter from Voltaire to Rousseau
, August 30, 1755. CW III.102; CC III.317.157. Rousseau himself
invited such barbs in a long author’s note of the
Second Discourse
. Although the note argues that there
are “far better reasons to state in affirming that man is a biped” rather than a quadruped, his lengthy
discussion prompted Voltaire’s famously biting dismissal. See:
Second Discourse
(Note III). CW
III.68-71; OC III.196-198.
535
Letter from Rousseau to Voltaire
, September 10, 1755. CW III.105; OC III.226.
165
unexpected decoration hardened this resolve. As he laments in
The Confessions
,
“[t]he success of my first Writings had put me in fashion… [and] stirred up curiosity:
They wanted to know this bizarre man who sought out no one and cared about
nothing except living freely and happily in his way.”
536
Recognized with awards and
adulation, the subject of rampant “curiosity,” well on his way to best-selling
537
fame
throughout the continent, the
First Discourse
left Rousseau embroiled in the very life
he so passionately loathed.
Clearly discomforted, Jean-Jacques responded by reiterating his central
concern—society was a catalyst for corruption—in increasingly hyperbolic prose.
The
Second Discourse
, substantively similar to his prize-winning piece, proved
significantly more controversial. He attacked not simply the arts, but property, civil
society, human history itself. This forceful work garnered further notoriety and
increasing mistrust. Rousseau, a once-charming Luddite, had now ruffled far too
many feathers.
If this paradoxical stance set him on a path to literal solitude, a turning point
of sorts occurred in 1758 with his
Letter to d’Alembert
. The piece began with a bold
proclamation: “I am at fault if I have on this occasion taken up my pen without
necessity.”
538
In sharp contrast to the “vain philosophical chatter” of his
contemporaries, Rousseau claimed to illuminate “a practical truth important to a
whole people.”
539
The “truth” to which he alluded was the danger of a theater taking
root in his beloved Geneva.
536
The Confessions
. CW V.308; OC I.367.
537
This was, of course, prior to the publication of
Julie
,
or the New Heloise
.
538
Letter to d’Alembert
. CW X.253; OC V.3.
539
Letter to d’Alembert
. CW X.255; OC V.6.
166
What is curious is not that Rousseau rose to the defense of his fatherland—a
common practice prior to his renunciation of citizenship in 1763—but rather the
severity of his rebuttal. At first glance, Rousseau’s response outmatched on every
level (passion, persuasiveness, depth, thoughtfulness, length) d’Alembert’s passing
suggestions in an unremarkable
Encyclopédie
entry on Geneva.
540
How, then, could
this parenthetical interjection have elicited such a powerful reaction? Why did
Rousseau really take up his pen in arms?
The Genevan described his motivation with a mix of self-deprecation and
obligation: “My [Swiss] compatriots have no need of my advice; I know it well. But
I have need to do myself honor in showing that I think as they do about our
maxims.”
541
In scribing
d’Alembert
, Rousseau’s humility was overcome by his sense
of obligation. Guided by honorific duty, he addressed an issue important, if not to a
whole people, than certainly to his fellow
citoyens
.
Most striking in this brief introduction to
d’Alembert
is the seriousness with
which Rousseau gauged the significance of his efforts. He considered the idea of a
Genevan theatre a matter of grave importance, an instance when the false
consciousness and alienation born of theatrical performance threatened the city in
which he found an exemplar of modern civic virtue. The idea of a Swiss stage did not
offend Rousseau because he putatively rejected theater (he had himself written
several
petit
dramas, and directly dismisses such charges towards the end of
540
The phrase that incensed Rousseau is as follows: “
Genève
auroit des spectacles & des moeurs, &
joüiroit de l'avantage des uns & des autres: les représentations théâtrales formeroient le goût des
citoyens, & leur donneroient une finesse de tact, une délicatesse de sentiment qu'il est très - difficile
d'acquérir sans ce secours; la littérature en profiteroit, sans que le libertinage fît des progrès, &
Genève
réuniroit à la sagesse de Lacédémone la politesse d'Athènes.” Diderot,
Encyclopédie
, Tome VII, pp.
576-577. It is generally recognized that Voltaire had “planted” this suggestion, as part of his broader
campaign to bring theater to Geneva.
541
Letter to d’Alembert
. CW X.255; OC V.6.
167
d’Alembert
). Instead, a theater in Switzerland posed very real dangers to the body of
its people: to its virtuous
salon
culture and civil society, to its economic welfare and
harmonious social fabric. What therefore drove Rousseau to write in this instance
was his self-described citizen’s duty to defend civic virtue.
That he wrote this work as an expatriate in France, and that he denounced one
of the few
philosophes
who would later defend him following the tumultuous
reception of
Emile
and
The Social Contract
, is no small matter. Rousseau, the self-
imposed exile defending a city in which he would never again settle, attacked the
work of a fellow intellectual relatively sympathetic to his writings.
542
These
circumstances did not go unnoticed. On September 29, 1758, in his
own
letter to
d’Alembert, Voltaire charged Jean-Jacques with “a double ingratitude.” In attacking
both “an art which he practices himself” and an author who had “overwhelmed him
with praises,” Voltaire decried Rousseau as an ingrate far more concerned with
garnering attention than demonstrating loyalty to his friends, or adhering to his
ideals.
543
Jean-Jacques was unprincipled, sensationalist, and eminently
untrustworthy; he was, in brief, a maverick unleashed, “a Diogène barking.”
544
Voltaire here compares Rousseau to Diogenes the Cynic, one of the most
flamboyant figures in the history of Western philosophy. Diogenes earned his
542
By relative, I am comparing d’Alembert’s sympathy for Rousseau with those of his peers—notably,
Diderot, Voltaire and Holbach. On June 15, 1762, d’Alembert wrote Rousseau to assure him that the
French peoples applauded
The Social Contract
and
Emile
. d’Alembert was the only
philosophe
to
offer such support, save Charles Duclos. In
The Confessions
, Rousseau seems characteristically
ungrateful, harping on the fact that d’Alembert had not signed the letter. For Rousseau’s account see:
The Confessions
, OC I.574; CW V.480. Quoted in Cranston,
The Solitary Self
, pp. 2-3. d’Alembert’s
letter appears in CC XI.1874.82-84.
543
We must again recall Voltaire’s complicity in d’Alembert’s
Genève
article, and his own vested
interest in establishing a Genevan theater. Quoted in Cranston,
The Noble Savage
, p. 137.
544
Quoted in Ibid., p. 137. From Besterman XIX.D7842. See: Diogenes Laertius,
Lives of Eminent
Philosophers: Volume II
, pp. 23-85.
168
infamous reputation as a “mad dog” and a “Socrates gone mad” from spectacles such
as masturbating in a public marketplace and urinating on a taunting crowd.
545
Although Rousseau had earlier
546
denounced the Cynic as a conspicuously absurd
figure, their resemblance was commonly noted by the
philosophes
and even
Rousseau’s later admirers.
547
In his lectures on ethics, for example, Kant labeled
Rousseau a “subtle Diogenes” whose work captured the Cynic “ideal of innocence or
rather simplicity.”
548
Whether affirmed in malice or praise, the similarities seemed
obvious to those familiar with both men. As Heinrich Niehues-Pröbsting
summarizes, “[t]he transition from Diogenes to Rousseau suggested itself, especially
since Rousseau seemed to follow the tracks of the Cynic in his cultural critique and
the idealization of untouched nature in the first and second
Discours
.”
549
In short—
and despite his own deeply personal interest in establishing a Genevan theater—
Voltaire had a point.
Rousseau nonetheless actively resisted such comparisons.
550
If the likenesses
were as obvious and ubiquitous as Niehues-Pröbsting believes, Jean-Jacques turned a
blind eye. He directly refers to Diogenes only thrice in his major works: in the
545
Both aliases were given him by Plato. See: Laertius, VI.40 & VI.54 (pp. 41 & 55). For Diogenes’
exploits see: VI.69 & VI.46 (pp. 71 & 27).
546
Preface to Narcisse
. CW II.191; OC II.965.
547
Heinrich Niehues-Pröbsting, “The Modern Reception of Cynicism: Diogenes in the
Enlightenment,” in
The Cynics: The Cynic Movement in Antiquity and Its Legacy
, R. Bracht Branham
and Marie-Odile Goulet-Cazé, eds. (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1996), p. 340.
548
Ibid., p. 340.
549
Ibid., p. 340. In support, he cites Maximilian Forschner’s 1977 work
Rousseau
, and Jean
Starobinski’s article “Diderot’s Satire ‘Rameau’s Neffe” (in
Das Rettende in der Gefahr: Kunstgriffe
der Aufklärung
, 1990).
550
In circuitous fashion, Rousseau describes his Cynical attitude as a sort of temporary insanity
brought on by urban living. After leaving Paris for Montmorency, he notes that “the spectacle of that
big City’s vices ceased to nourish the indignation it had inspired in me. When I no longer saw men, I
ceased to despise them; when I no longer saw the wicked I ceased to hate them. My heart, which is
hardly formed for hatred, could no longer do anything but deplore their misery… and, without anyone
noticing it, almost without noticing it myself, I again became fearful, accommodating, timid, in a word
the same Jean-Jacques I had been before.”
The Confessions
. CW V.350; OC I.417.
169
Preface to Narcisse
, the
Second Discourse
, and
The Dialogues
.
551
In
Narcisse
,
Diogenes is quickly dismissed as a typical self-promoting philosopher.
552
In the
Dialogues
, Rousseau refutes the charge that his onetime career as a music-copyist
was “an affectation of simplicity or poverty to copy an Epictetus or Diogenes” as
many had claimed.
553
Only in the
Discourse
does Rousseau demonstrate even
passing sympathy with the Cynic’s agenda: he concludes that “the reason Diogenes
did not find a man was that he sought amongst his contemporaries the man of a time
that no longer existed.”
554
Rousseau here refers to the famous anecdote, recorded by Diogenes Laertius,
that Diogenes “lit a lamp in broad daylight and said, as he went about, ‘I am looking
for a man.’”
555
Rousseau’s affinity for this spectacle seems logical enough. If
virtuous men were hard to find in ancient Athens, they were (he often reminded)
nearly extinct in eighteenth-century Paris.
556
Where Diogenes took to the streets,
Rousseau took to his pen. In both cases, onlookers were asked to judge themselves
551
Rousseau also refers to Diogenes in a letter written to Laurent Aymont de Franquières dated
January 15, 1769. In it, Rousseau expresses a classically Cynical emphasis on action: “I think that
everyone will be judged not concerning what he has believed, but concerning what he has done.”
Later in the letter, he offers cautious praise of Diogenes who, in a fashion atypical of philosophers,
followed his conscience when refuting Zeno: “Was it not this alone which made Diogenes walk as his
only reply before Zeno who was denying movement?” See:
Letter to Franquières
. CW VIII.262 &
264; OC IV.1137 & 1139.
552
Preface to Narcisse
. CW II.191; OC II.965.
553
Dialogues
. CW I.132; OC I.830.
554
It is worth noting that in the very next sentence, Rousseau evokes Cato—
not
Diogenes—as “the
greatest of men” and a paragon of virtue “out of place in his century.” See:
Second Discourse
. CW
III.65; OC III.192.
555
Laertius, VI.41 (p. 43). This was a recurring theme in Diogenes’ repertoire. Laertius records two
other incidents with similar messages. First: when the Cynic is “asked where in Greece he saw good
men, he replied, ‘Good men nowhere, but good boys at Lacedaemon.’” (VI.27) And second: “One day
he shouted out for men, and when people collected, hit out at them with his stick, saying, ‘It was men I
called for, not scoundrels.’” (VI.32)
556
Fénelon—whom Rousseau praised in the
Dialogues
as a virtuous man who “did honor to modern
times”—provided one of the few notable exceptions to this rule. CW I.158; OC I.863-864.
170
against the weight of the accusation, to measure themselves against a standard of
(natural) virtue far removed from their actual (social) condition.
At heart of these critiques was a shared appreciation of the self-sufficient life
lived in greater accord with nature, and a vision of virtue rooted in simple adherence
to this ideal. Yet if the Cynic preached simplicity as an antidote to society’s
corruptions, his life—like Rousseau’s—was anything but. Indeed, even Diogenes’
unlikely path to philosophy was characteristically colorful. Forced to flee his native
Sinope over a money-laundering scandal and sold into slavery, this sudden escape
transformed a banker’s greedy son into an unruly philosophic gadfly.
557
It was
precisely his exile that forced him to seek “the means of adapting himself to
circumstances” which he found in a strenuous model of philosophy aimed at inuring
himself to misfortune.
558
As with Rousseau, the Cynic began his career as a foreigner in an urbane city.
Set adrift in Athens (the Paris to Sparta’s Geneva), Diogenes grew disturbed by the
decadence of his surroundings. He reacted by embracing hardship as a catalyst for
self-sufficiency, and shunning the shallow pleasures (physical comfort, refined
appearance, gluttony) in which his peers indulged. This aggressive asceticism taught
him to become “capable of overcoming anything,”
559
a resiliency he pressed upon his
557
As Laertius recounts, Diogenes fled Sinope (a port town in northern Turkey on the Black Sea
peninsula) “because his father [the banker Hicesius] was entrusted with the money of the state and
adultered the coinage.” Several accounts report very different findings: that Diogenes himself
confessed to the crime; that he was coerced by workmen to do so; that the Delphic oracle gave him
permission to alter currency and he mistook the god’s words. See: Laertius, VI.20-21 (p. 23).
558
Ibid., VI.22 (p. 25). “When someone reproached [Diogenes] with his exile,” Laertius writes, “his
reply was, ‘Nay, it was through that, you miserable fellow, that I came to be a philosopher.’” VI.49 (p.
51).
559
Ibid., VI.71 (p. 73).
171
students by insisting they conform to a Spartan standard of living.
560
He told a
perfumed boy that sweet smells might “cause an ill odor in your life.”
561
He hugged
snowy statues on cold days. He made a bed of a bathtub, and begged to a statue “to
get practice in being refused.”
562
By all accounts, Diogenes “was great at pouring scorn on his
contemporaries.”
563
And like Rousseau, he saved his sharpest contempt for the
privileged classes. “He would,” Laertius recounts, “ridicule good birth and fame and
all such distinctions, calling them showy ornaments of vice.”
564
The marks of wealth
signaled corruption: dependence upon trivial comforts and self-gratification, the
antithesis of the Cynic ideal of
autarkeia
.
565
Diogenes was particularly hostile
towards philosophical esotericism, then epitomized by the teachings of Plato.
566
Similar to Rousseau, the Cynic denigrated the value of philosophic discourse, arguing
that actions spoke infinitely louder than words and were far more useful in teaching
virtue. This is why he labeled a man who had requested his writings “a simpleton,”
chiding “you do not choose painted figs, but real ones; and yet you pass over the true
training and would apply yourself to written rules.”
567
Clearly, philosophy rings
hollow if preached but not practiced, just as wisdom is worthless if disconnected from
560
As Laertius recounts, “he taught them to wait upon themselves, and to be content with plain fare
and water to drink. He used to make them crop their hair close and to wear it unadorned, and to go
lightly clad, barefoot, silent, and not looking about them in the streets.” Ibid., VI.31 (p. 33).
561
Ibid., VI.66 (p. 69).
562
Ibid., VI.49 (p. 51).
563
Ibid., VI.24 (p. 27).
564
Ibid., VI.72 (p. 75).
565
Often translated as “self-sufficiency.” This is a value championed by Rousseau as the basis of
independence.
Autarchy
was also a Stoic ideal, a “moral argument” Starobinski describes as the lesson
that “the soul must seek its gratifications within itself and among its own
possessions
, without calling
upon outside assistance.” See: Starobinski, pp. 104-105.
566
According to Laertius, Diogenes regularly reproached Plato. In one example the Cynic ridiculed
Plato’s theory of the forms, quipping that “table and cup I see; but your tablehood and cuphood… I can
nowise see.” Ibid., VI.53 (p. 55).
567
Ibid., VI.48 (p. 51).
172
life. As if to punctuate his point, Diogenes (unlike Rousseau) left no writings: he
conveyed lessons solely through vivid, often outrageous exhibitionism.
568
Exiled in a decadent land, the Cynic’s flamboyant strategy served a concrete
pedagogical purpose. In order to demonstrate the folly of society, he acted out; in
order to present a more virtuous alternative, he led by example; in order to disturb the
status quo, he embraced absurd excess. Furthermore, by welcoming difficulty (and
not simply ignoring hardship), he offered constant reminders of his integrity.
To validate his own writings, Rousseau likewise had to lead by example.
Following the embrace of his
First Discourse
, he had no choice but to reiterate his
resistance to society’s corrupting influence; withdrawal offered proof of his critical
detachment and testified to the sincerity of his writings. What Voltaire dismissed as
hyperbole and ingratitude, Rousseau understood as the only honest position for one of
his beliefs. In striking a self-distanced stance he stood much as Diogenes did two
centuries prior, carrying a proverbial lantern through the streets of Paris to illuminate
the failings of his peers. With the original Cynic’s force and righteous moral zeal,
Rousseau dared his readers to confront the dire direction human history had taken,
and perhaps join him in standing apart.
* * * * *
Like his Pagan forebear Diogenes, Rousseau challenged his contemporaries to
assess themselves and embrace the simple virtues of a more natural subsistence. He
did so as an outsider, yet one deeply involved with the society whose welfare he so
568
Most of what we know today about Diogenes comes to us from the anecdotes collected by the
ancient Greek historian Laertius.
173
steadfastly served. In a similarly dissonant manner, Rousseau’s role as a recluse drew
upon conflicting traditions: the demonstrative stance of Cynical exile, a Pelagian
vision of natural goodness, and the moralizing tone of an Edenic narrative.
Following the
Second Discourse
, Rousseau maintained this precarious
balancing act. Redoubling his efforts he published longer, more personally revealing,
more ambitious works that touched upon the theme of reclusiveness. Some of these
efforts were explicit addendums to earlier writings. The
Essay on the Origin of
Languages
, for example, was described in a prefatory draft as being “at first merely a
fragment of the discourse on inequality which I omitted from it as too long and out of
place.”
569
Revised several times before completion in 1763,
570
the
Essay
revisited
Rousseau’s idyllic depiction of the natural state:
Assume a perpetual spring on earth; assume water, livestock,
pasturage everywhere; assume men leaving the hands of nature, once
dispersed throughout all this; I cannot imagine how they would ever
have renounced their primitive freedom and forsaken the isolated and
pastoral life so suited to their natural indolence, in order needlessly to
impose on themselves the slavery, the labors, the miseries inseparable
from the social state.
571
The bounty and freedom of nature is matched only by the “slavery” and “miseries” of
society. A study of extremes, Rousseau is hard-pressed to find a reasonable
explanation for our socialization. Yet the effects of this revolutionary event are clear:
569
Essay on the Origin of Languages
. CW VII.289; OC V.373.
570
Believed to have been completed in 1763, dating the
Essay on the Origin of Languages
(as well as
determining its relation to the
Second Discourse
) is a matter of some dispute amongst Rousseau
scholars. For a concise discussion of these matters, see: CW VII.xxvii-xxviii. For two major critical
discussions of the significance of the
Essay
in relation to both Western thought and Rousseau’s
oeuvres
, see (respectively): Jacques Derrida,
Of Grammatology
, Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, tr.
(Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1974); and Jean Starobinski, “Rousseau and the Origin of
Languages,” in
Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Transparency and Obstruction
.
571
Essay on the Origin of Languages
. CW VII.310; OC V.400-401.
174
the earth of God’s creation was now “adorned or disfigured by the hands of man.”
572
For Rousseau, this development was born of desire rather than practical necessity. As
he laments, “[t]he first languages, daughters of pleasure and not of need, long bore
the sign of their father; their seductive accent faded only with the feelings that had
caused them to arise, when new needs introduced among men forced each to consider
only himself and to withdraw his heart within himself.”
573
Although “[s]peech distinguishes man from the animals”
574
and thus
constitutes an intrinsic human faculty, its spontaneous advent led us down a slippery
slope. Once introduced, language evolved from an expression of natural sexual desire
to a catalyst for self-interest, from the simple spontaneous outpour of
amour
to the
corrupting influence of
amour propre
. The
Essay on the Origin of Languages
reinforced what the
Second Discourse
had already made plain: speech, like society,
had innocent origins and unvirtuous consequences.
In both works, Rousseau refused to abandon a provocative dialectic: man may
be naturally good, but his socializing inventions were deeply flawed. Having led us
far astray from the idyll pastures of our natural content, the gravest consequence of
this transition was moral. Consider Rousseau’s “golden rule” as taken from the
Second Discourse
: “
Do what is good for you with the least possible harm to
others
.”
575
This negative sense of freedom recurs in
Emile
: “O what good is
necessarily done to his fellows by the one among them, if there is such a one, who
never does them harm! What an intrepid soul, what a vigorous character he needs for
572
Essay on the Origin of Languages
. CW VII.312; OC V.403-404.
573
Essay on the Origin of Languages
. CW VII.315; OC V.407.
574
Essay on the Origin of Languages
. CW VII.289; OC V.375.
575
Second Discourse
. CW III.38; OC III.156.
175
that! It is not in reasoning about this maxim, but in trying to put it into practice, that
one feels how great it is and how difficult of success.”
576
The problem lies in the practice. How might we protect individual freedom in
society, particularly in congested urban cities such as Paris? Perhaps, as Emile’s
tutelage suggests, through withdrawal. Given the terms of freedom, solitude adopts a
practical value underscored by a moral dimension. Isolated, we literally cannot harm
peers with whom we have no contact; and in not causing another grief, we both act
morally and revive some measure of natural goodness in a denatured world.
Rousseau affirmed the value of retreat in an author’s note in
Emile
:
The precept of never hurting another carries with it that of being
attached to human society as little as possible, for in the social state the
good of one necessarily constitutes the harm of another. This relation
is in the essence of the thing, and nothing can change it. On the basis
of this principle, let one investigate who is the better: the social man or
the solitary man. An illustrious author says it is only the wicked man
who is alone. I say that it is only the good man who is alone. If this
proposition is less sententious, it is truer and better reasoned than the
former one. If the wicked man were alone, what harm would he do?
It is in society that he sets up his devices for hurting others.
577
In addition to clarifying his position, this paragraph offered a direct rebuttal to a line
in Diderot’s play
Le fils naturel
. Written shortly after Rousseau’s withdrawal to
Montmorency, Diderot condemned solitude as the misguided reverie of a wicked
misanthrope:
578
“Il n' y a que le méchant qui soit seul.”
579
Clearly, Rousseau
576
Emile
. E 105.
577
Emile
. E 105.
578
For Rousseau’s recollections of the incident see:
The Confessions
. OC I.455-456;
Dialogues
. OC
I.788-789. Readers might also compare Rousseau’s “golden rule” to Plato’s
Republic
, (I.335e) where,
during a discussion of justice, Socrates concludes that “it has become apparent to us that it is never just
to harm anyone.”
579
The full sentence is actually quite inflammatory. Dderot’s character Constance uses a Rousseauist
argument (an ‘appeal to the heart’) to convince Dorval (a character based on Rousseau) that the “good
man” exists only in society: “J'en appelle à votre coeur; interrogez-le; et il vous dira que l'homme de
bien est dans la société, et qu' il n' y a que le méchant qui soit seul.” From
Le fils naturel
, Act IV,
176
disagreed. Instead, it was “only the good man who is alone.” Who is more harmful
to his fellow citizens? Whose actions are more likely to jeopardize the welfare and
freedom of others? A man removed from society, or a man caught within its
nefarious webs?
Emile
argues unequivocally for the former. Turning upon the principle of
fortitude through solitude, the pupil’s education is an attempt to instill virtue in a
child raised in accord with his innocent nature. In the final paragraph of Book III, the
tutor summarizes Emile’s accomplishments. The carefully reared youth is a model
individual: “He considers himself without regard to others and finds it good that
others do not think of him. He demands nothing of anyone and believes he owes
nothing to anyone. He is alone in human society; he counts himself alone. More than
anyone else, he has the right to count on himself, for he is all that one can be at his
age.”
580
Here, then, is Rousseau’s idealized solitaire, a child raised sheltered from
society. Retreat has cultivated a faultless individual, one with “no errors,” “no vices,”
“a healthy body, agile limbs, a precise and unprejudiced mind, a heart that is free and
without passions.”
581
Most significantly, “
amour-propre
, the first and most natural of
all the passions, is still hardly aroused in him. Without troubling the repose of
anyone, he has lived satisfied, happy, and free insofar as nature has permitted.”
582
In
short, he is free at the expense of no one.
Yet this solitary bliss seems fatefully impermanent. After all, Rousseau
reminds us, our sociability is a necessary evil. We have little choice in the matter; our
Scene 3. In:
Diderot: Œuvres
,
Tome IV
, p. 1113. For Rousseau’s reaction to this “scathing and harsh
sentence without any qualification” see:
The Confessions
. CW V.382; OC I.455.
580
Emile
. E 208.
581
Emile
. E 208.
582
Emile
. E 208.
177
very natures are defined by our interdependence. “It is man’s weakness which makes
him sociable; it is our common miseries which turn our hearts to humanity,” he
explains. Yet “we would owe humanity nothing [only] if we were not men.”
583
Only
God—completely independent and a model of perfect solitude—has no need of
others. Man has no such luxury. “Every attachment is a sign of insufficiency,”
Rousseau laments. “If each of us had no need of others, he would hardly think of
uniting himself with them. Thus from our very infirmity is born our frail
happiness.”
584
Yet without this “very infirmity,” we would not be human. Much as
Rousseau might admire
Robinson Crusoe
, the lesson is clear: no man is an island.
Put more strongly, every man has need of others.
Evoking classical voluntarist descriptions of God as a completely self-
sufficient, perfectly ordered whole unto himself, Rousseau reminds us that man is a
far cry from such perfection: “A truly happy being is a solitary being. God alone
enjoys an absolute happiness. But who among us has the idea of it?”
585
By our very
natures, no one; our mutual dependence defines our humanity. It is from this honest
assessment that Rousseau’s vision of reform flows. He seeks to change our
conventions, not our natures, employing the very faculties that have precipitated our
fall from natural grace to legitimize the “chains” of our necessary attachments.
586
However, to move forward we must sometimes first withdraw. Under dire
social circumstances and extreme social pressures, retreat provides a politically useful
action. Near the end of
Emile
, exile is presented as a necessary stage in the pupil’s
583
Emile
. E 221.
584
Emile
. E 221.
585
Emile
. E 221.
586
To wit, such is the guiding principle of the general will under which self-interested individualism is
applied in service of the common good.
178
carefully planned pedagogy. Ringing a clearly autobiographical note, the tutor
describes with some melancholy a situation very much like Rousseau’s own:
There are circumstances in which a man can be more useful to his
fellow citizens outside of his fatherland than if he were living in its
bosom. Then he ought to listen only to his zeal and to endure his exile
without grumbling. This exile itself is one of his duties.
587
As an allusion to Rousseau’s own life, the lines read as a justification for his flight
from Geneva. Exile offers not an excuse for “grumbling,” but a civic duty to be
accepted as the “most useful” means of serving a greater good (his
patrie
).
Reiterating the utility of retreat, the tutor surmises that “[a]ll men who withdraw from
the hub of society are useful precisely because they withdraw from it, since its vices
come from its being overpopulated. They are even more useful when they can bring
life, cultivation, and the love of their first state to forsaken places.”
588
His
justification is twofold. First, withdrawal serves a pragmatic aim: depopulating
“overpopulated” society and diminishing the congestion conducive to social vices.
And second, the recluse can act as a type of ambassador. Removed from their
homelands, stuck in “forsaken” cultures, their status and experience as outsiders
allows them to import “life, cultivation, and the love of their first state.”
Exile is also a casualty of serving the truth, the very pursuit to which
Rousseau had dedicated his life. In his
Fragments autobiographiques
, he
underscored the lonely, sacrificial fruits born of this calling: “Persecution has
elevated my soul. I feel that the love of truth has become dear to me because it has
cost me dearly. Perhaps at first it was no more than a system for me, now it is my
587
Emile
. E 474.
588
Emile
. E 474.
179
dominant passion… the most noble that can befall the heart of man.”
589
Emile has no
such bittersweet burden to bear:
But you, good Emile, on whom nothing imposes these painful
sacrifices, you who have not taken on the sad job of telling the truth to
men, go and live in their midst, cultivate their friendship in sweet
association, be their benefactor and their model. Your example will
serve them better than all our books, and the good they see you do will
touch them more than all our vain speeches.”
590
Privileged with the self-sufficiency and sound judgment of an isolated education, free
of the truth-bearer’s onus, Emile must reemerge, return from withdrawal and act as a
beacon amongst men, a “benefactor” and “model” applying his virtuous education to
the service of his fellow citizens.
After all, he
must
reenter society. This is the final lesson pressed upon the
pupil, and one whose events unfold to disastrous consequences in
Emile
’s sequel,
Les
solitaires
. Harping on this outcome, Judith Shklar reads in Rousseau a deep and
unflinching pessimism. Taking a grim view of his worldview, one which “offers no
occasion for happiness or civic virtue,”
591
Shklar notes the dismal failures of Emile
and Sophie to live amongst their peers: “The happy end of
Emile
is false,… and
Emile’s character cannot reveal itself until he
really
becomes a man, that is, a
suffering victim.”
592
As Rousseau readily admits, man surely suffers: “Always more
suffering than enjoyment; this relation between the two is common to all men. Man’s
felicity on earth is, hence, only a negative condition; the smallest number of ills he
can suffer ought to constitute its measure.”
593
Furthermore, this condition is
589
Fragments autobiographiques
(18). OC I.1164.
590
Emile
. E 474.
591
Shklar,
Men and Citizens
, p. 214.
592
Ibid., p. 235.
593
Emile
. E 80.
180
symptomatic of human desire, a negative need defined by want or lack that “supposes
privation, and all sensed privations are painful.”
594
Given this dour assessment, we might well be tempted to follow Shklar’s lead
and read Rousseau’s ontology as a manifesto of victimization. But rather than
succumb to the weight of his own analysis, he describes how we may yet attain a
measure of peace. As he writes in
Emile
,
In what, then, consists human wisdom or the road of true happiness?
It is not precisely in diminishing our desires, for if they were beneath
our power, a part of our faculties would remain idle, and we would not
enjoy our whole being. Neither is it in extending our faculties, for if,
proportionate to them, our desires were more extended, we would as a
result only become unhappier. But it is in diminishing the excess of
the desires over the faculties and putting power and will in perfect
equality. It is only then that, with all the powers in action, the soul
will nevertheless remain peaceful and that man will be well ordered.
595
Here is the lesson of the
Second Discourse
, concisely captured: contentment is
possible only if our desires do not exceed our abilities to satiate them. To achieve
this balance we must accept, not lament, our natural limits as human beings. We
must, to paraphrase
The Social Contract
, recognize what we are while striving to
realize what we should be.
596
“What is more,” Rousseau elaborates, diminishing the distance between our
wants and needs conforms to the will of God: “the Author of things provides not only
for the needs He gives us but also for those we give ourselves; and it is in order to
place desire always at the side of need that He causes our tastes to change and be
594
Emile
. E 80.
595
Emile
. E 80.
596
Again,
The Social Contract
’s opening phrase—“I want to inquire whether there can be a legitimate
and reliable rule of administration in the civil order, taking men as they are and laws as they can be”—
establishes the dialectic between heuristic idealism and pessimistic realism that guides much of
Rousseau’s work.
The Social Contract
. CW IV.131; OC III.351.
181
modified with our ways of life.”
597
In society, our wants far outpace our needs.
Rather than increase this artificial imbalance, we must recognize the virtue of self-
restraint and contain the excess of desires that so disserves denatured man.
598
As is often the case with Rousseau, he couples unflinching criticism with
programmatic optimism, an exegesis of how things are with a vision of how they
could be better. We should not therefore conflate his deep mistrust of society with
abject pessimism. As with Diogenes, Rousseau’s harsh criticism was fueled by
concern; the depth of his remorse spoke to the necessity of active reform (rather than
debilitating misery). Similarly, retreat must not be confused with misanthropy; if
anything, Rousseau loved far too deeply. In this, he was
not
alone. Taking recourse
in solitude, he followed a Christian tradition in which withdrawal offers protection
from temptation, allowing men to contemplate God while sheltered from the sinful
distractions of society. To clarify this point, we need only examine the hagiography
of a Stylite.
Some fifteen hundred years before Rousseau, when martyrs cared little for
writing or reception, Saint Antony fled society to resist Satan’s sway. After retreating
to a cave for twenty years, immersed in a life of self-imposed hardship, living on a
strict diet of bread, salt and water while shunning humans and demons alike, Antony
emerged with a clear sense of dutiful purpose: live humbly, do not fear hardship,
place faith wholly in God. “Virtue exists when the soul maintains its intellectual part
597
Emile
. E 151.
598
By Rousseau’s description, aligning our wants and needs serves both God and humankind; it
reflects a deference to the divine will, and limits the self-destructive consequences of excessive desire.
182
according to nature,” he writes, “when it remains as it was made—and it was made
beautiful and perfectly straight.”
599
Predating Rousseau’s praise of natural harmony, Antony describes the human
soul as God’s handiwork (and “God made nothing bad”).
600
The virtuous life
therefore demands that our minds embrace the divine model latent within our spirits.
The challenge Antony imposes upon himself—and others seeking heavenly
redemption—is to keep evil at bay, to resist the Devil’s malicious attempts to corrupt
our pure relationships with God. External and internal fortitude are demanded of a
holy battle against evil (personified by demons), where integrity is not merely an
eventual aim but an ever-present necessity to resist corruption.
For Antony, as with both Rousseau and Diogenes, such enlightened fortitude
is not borne of scholarly rigor. Rather, he proposes a decidedly anti-intellectual
vision of wisdom, declaring that “none of us is judged for what he does not know, any
more than one is counted blessed because he is learned and possesses knowledge.”
601
Sincere observance, undying faith, and (above all) prayer are the true means of self-
betterment, for they offer proof of virtue (enlightened action), inspire personal
determination, and solicit God’s spiritual support. Indeed, “for those in whom the
action through faith is present, the demonstration through argument is unnecessary,
perhaps even useless.”
602
True faith is demonstrated by certitude, stability and consistency, no matter
the corporeal challenges. If cultivating such strenuous devotion requires a concrete
599
Athanasius,
The Life of Antony and the Letter to Marcellinus
, Robert C. Gregg, tr. (Mahwah, NJ:
Paulist Press, 1980), p. 46.
600
Ibid., p. 47.
601
Ibid., p. 57.
602
Ibid., p. 87.
183
model, Antony offers an unflinching example. While God is benevolent, a prolific
author of righteous covenants, he is unfortunately much duller than the Devil. And it
is this demon’s outrageous efforts to corrupt that dictate the severe terms of faith. His
efforts to tempt and torture the Desert Saint range from sloppy (throwing silver plates
in his path) to severe (unleashing the apparitions of vicious beasts on his body).
“How many wrestlings he endured… against destructive demons”
603
in the desert, yet
he maintained his poise and hurled holy words at them, and “they fled, being driven
away by the remark as by a whip.”
604
The desert molds Antony into a warrior monk,
a hero-hermit who fights Satan’s many forms—greed, pride, doubt, deterrence,
disgust, and lust—with righteous resistance strengthened by the courage of his
convictions.
His methods proved wildly popular. A social loner, Antony drew stadium-
sized crowds to observe him perched on a desert pole, where he won many over with
physical proofs of the benefits of his faith (dispelling the demons of a man’s
daughter, inspiring his sister’s virginity, foreseeing a despot’s death). The ubiquity of
Christian conversion only strengthened his resolve to serve God and spread His
teachings no matter the consequences. As Antony confidently argued, “the faith and
teaching of Christ, ridiculed… and persecuted frequently by rulers, has [nonetheless]
filled the world.”
605
In spite of opposition, followers in every land had come to
embrace the glorious truth of Christ.
No stranger to persecution, Rousseau also found solace in the physical proofs
of his convictions. As evidence he looked to nature, a testament of God’s
603
Ibid., p. 69.
604
Ibid., p. 70.
605
Ibid., p. 88.
184
magnificence far more compelling than academic arguments or the catechisms of
Clerics. As with Antony, Rousseau found virtue in abandoning himself to a perfect
order. Yet because both recognized the imminence of temptation, be it the Devil’s
seductive measures or society’s provocative pleasures (theater, recognition, wealth),
they framed this quest in terms of aggressive isolation. Both saw training as a
necessary stage in the service of higher truths, a means of self-fortification to remain
steadfast in the face of corruption. And for Antony and Rousseau alike, the courage
of their convictions was strengthened by looking inwards.
Furthermore, in both instances retreat was incomplete without reentry—
returning to the belly of the beast, to a society prone to vice, as a living model of man
redeemed. Antony returned from the mountains. Emile was reared as society’s
prodigal son. Even Rousseau (the citizen of Geneva) fancied himself an exemplar of
sorts in France. Yet while Emile’s imaginary fate is a matter of speculation,
Rousseau’s was not.
Just as Antony was followed and worshipped as a martyr to the truth,
Rousseau was also revered throughout Europe, inundated with letters of praise and
the author of his century’s bestselling novel.
606
His popularity amongst readers
notwithstanding, the publication of
Emile
and
The Social Contract
met with almost
immediate censure and led, quite suddenly, to his unplanned retreat. If Rousseau had
seriously struggled to apply his ideas in practice, if he had praised withdrawal as a
means to a civic end, he would have no chance to return bearing hope. Twelve years
after the
First Discourse
took top prize at Dijon, Jean-Jacques was delivered a harsh
606
Namely,
Julie
. See: Darnton,
The Great Cat Massacre and Other Episodes in French Cultural
Histor
.
185
reproach: served with arrest papers and forced from his home, society had finally
begged his leave.
* * * * *
From the sociological exegesis of his discourses, to the remote, self-styled
community of
Julie
,
607
to
Emile’s
virtuous education sheltered from society,
608
to his
final bittersweet ode to solitude in the
Reveries
, Jean-Jacques’ mistrust of social
attachments grew ever more insistent and decidedly more personal. Contemporary
society had not only evolved contrary to man’s best interests; it had also done
Rousseau a great personal injustice.
609
Alienated by fractured relationships with
friends and peers, condemned for subverting Catholic, aristocratic, and monarchal
values, Rousseau was increasingly a man on his own. Retreat was finally—and
unequivocally—pressed upon him following the 1762 publications of
Emile
and
The
Social Contract
. These books were burned from Paris to Geneva,
610
its author
criminalized for their content. Rousseau, the
wunderkind
who had denounced his
own startling fame, excommunicated himself from his social and intellectual
607
See, for example, Rousseau’s description of the Valais and his enchantment with the
disinterestedness of its inhabitants: “The most agreeable part of their welcome, it seemed to me, was to
detect in it not the slightest vestige of constraint either for them or for me. They lived in their homes
as if I was not there, and I was free to do as if I were there alone.” In this instance, solitude enables a
negative freedom, the lack of imposition of another’s will on his actions.
Julie
. CW VI 66; OC II.80-
81. Readers should compare this to Rousseau’s description of Geneva in his
Letter to d’Alembert
, in
which he stresses his native town’s independence as a mark of its freedom.
608
In contrast to
Emile
,
The Social Contract
envisions good citizens in a good society, a comparison
beyond the immediate scope of this piece.
609
Rousseau’s indignation was evident in nearly all of his writings after 1762, including the
Letter to
Beaumont
,
Letters Written From the Mountain
,
The Confessions
,
The Dialogues
, and
The Reveries of
the Solitary Walker
.
610
According to Rousseau, “
The Social Contract
was not burned anywhere except Geneva where it
was not printed.” The Genevan magistrates were threatened by the work’s depiction of a constitution
that very much resembled their own, and far less concerned with the more controversial
Emile
.
Letters
Written From the Mountain
(Sixth Letter). CW IX.234; OC III.810.
186
community, and dared to attack both Papal and Enlightenment ideals, was now finally
forced to abscond from the society which had for so long served as the object of his
wrath.
Although this final stage of Rousseau’s life marked a bitter withdrawal from
society, he fled neither strictly of his own volition, nor into silence. On the morning
of June 9, 1762, Omer and Guillaume Joly de Fleury, Attorney-General and
Procurator-General of France, presented magistrate Maupeou’s Parlement with an
unequivocal indictment of Rousseau.
611
Condemning
Emile
(and, more precisely, its
deistic
Profession of Faith
) as subversive, seditious, impious and unholy, the brothers
de Fleury called for the immediate imprisonment and interrogation of its purportedly
blasphemous author.
612
The clock had not yet struck ten. More than six hours later,
when court officers arrived to execute their order by escorting Rousseau to the
Bastille, their fugitive was already in flight to Switzerland and, soon after, the
Prussian border.
Rousseau describes these events in great detail in
The Confessions
. He
greeted rumors of imminent legal proceedings with a mixture of stubbornness and
naïveté. “The dull roar that preceded the storm began to make itself heard and all
slightly perceptive people saw very well that some plot was brewing over the subject
611
Cranston,
The Noble Savage
, p. 358.
612
In the June 9 warrant issued for his arrest, the French Parlement accused Rousseau of promoting
“impious and detestable principles” contemptuous of religion, Church and King alike. From:
Extrait
des Registres du Parlement
,
Arrêt de la cour de Parlement
,
Qui condamne un Imprimé ayant pour titre
Émile
,
ou de l’Éducation
,
par J. J. Rousseau
,
imprimé à La Hage… M.DCC.LXII
.,
à être lacéré &
brûlé par l’Exécuteur de la Haute Justice
. The text is reproduced in the beginning of
Jean-Jacques
Rousseau, Citoyen à Genève, à Christophe de Beaumont, Archevêque de Paris, Duc de St. Cloud, Pair
de France, Commandeur de l’Ordre du St. Esprit, Proviseur de Sorbonne, &c
. (Amsterdam: Chez
Marc Michel Rey, 1763).
187
of my book [
Emile
] and myself that would not take long to burst out.”
613
Still, he
admits that he lacked such meager awareness: “my feeling of security, my stupidity
was such that, far from foreseeing my misfortune, I did not even suspect its cause
after I felt its effect.”
614
French authorities sounded warning as they “began by rather
skillfully circulating the idea that since they had dealt severely with the Jesuits they
could not show a partial indulgence for books and authors who attacked Religion.”
615
Sectarian tensions mounted, a development that acutely affected Rousseau’s own
creed. He learned in October, 1761 of the arrests of Francois Rouchette (a Protestant
pastor) and the Grenin brothers (three Protestant laymen) in Toulouse, all of whom
were executed weeks later.
616
Dark clouds were gathering yet Rousseau “remained calm.”
617
In spite of his
megalomaniac paranoia—he speaks of “plots” hatched against him by
“Holbachians,”
618
certain that “it was very much me they were after”
619
—he still
613
The Confessions
. CW V.481-482; OC 575.
614
The Confessions
. CW V.482; OC 575.
615
The Confessions
. CW V.482; OC 575-6.
616
The letter warning Rousseau was from fellow Protestant Jean Ribotte, who asked Rousseau to
publish a manifesto on behalf of religious tolerance and write an appeal to the provincial Governor
Duc de Richelieu. Rousseau refused, citing the Pauline doctrine of compliance. Ribotte also made the
same request of Voltaire, who failed to act before the executions. For Ribotte’s letter see: CC IX.1498.
For Rousseau’s response see: CC IX.1521. For a concise account of these events see: Cranston,
The
Noble Savage
, pp. 299-301. It is also worth noting that only two months later, Ribotte alerted both
Rousseau and Voltaire of the infamous Calas affair, again begging their intervention. On October 13,
1761, Huguenot merchant Jean Calas had discovered his oldest son dead (by hanging) in his Toulouse
shop. Attributing the death to suicide, Calas was charged by local magistrates with murdering the
youth to prevent him from converting to Catholicism. Incited by a wave of religious (and anti-
Huguenot) intolerance throughout the region, Calas was condemned to death on March 9, 1762, and
publicly broken on the wheel, strangled, and burned the following day. The execution led Voltaire,
“
l’homme de Calas
,” to petition for religious tolerance. A panel of fifty judges was appointed to
review the case, and reversed the ruling on March 9, 1765. Although this affair marked a catalyst in
the reform of religious tolerance laws, it was not until 1787 that Louis XVI granted official tolerance to
the Huguenots, and 1905 that Church and State were officially made separate in France.
617
The Confessions
. CW V.482; OC I.576.
618
As “[t]he rumors increased and soon changed their tone” and “the threats became addressed directly
at me,” Rousseau admits that he “did not at all doubt that this [rumor of the Parlement’s censure] was
an invention of the Holbachians to seek to frighten me and to incite me to flee.” Rousseau is here
188
“could not resolve to flee.”
620
Yet he was forced to confront mounting evidence. In a
letter to M. le Maréchal from the Curate de Deuil, Jean-Jacques learned from a
reliable source that
Parlement was to proceed against me with the ultimate severity, and
that on a certain day, which he noted, a warrant would be issued for
my arrest. I judged this warrant to be of Holbachian fabrications; I
knew that Parlement was very attentive to legal formalities, and that to
begin on this occasion with a warrant of arrest, before knowing
juridically whether I acknowledged the book [
Emile
] and whether I
was really its author, was to violate all of them.
621
But
Emile
, like all of his major works save the
First Discourse
and
Julie
, was openly
inscribed with his name and self-appointed title: Jean-Jacques Rousseau,
Citoyen de
Genève
.
622
He had already corresponded with the censor Malesherbes over its
content, and had publicly wrangled with the French publisher Duchesne to ensure that
it went to press in a timely fashion.
623
The obviousness of the situation still seemed to escape Rousseau. Even after
friends warned him of imminent legal action, he stubbornly refused to accept the
increasing precariousness of his situation.
Since I felt very well that underneath all this there was some mystery
which they did not want to tell me, I calmly awaited the event,
referring to Baron d’Holbach, a prominent
philosophe
and avowed atheist.
The Confessions
. CW
V.482;OC I.576.
619
The Confessions
. CW V.483;OC I.577.
620
The Confessions
. CW V.484;OC I.578.
621
The Confessions
. CW V.484;OC I.578.
622
The
Discourse on the Sciences and Arts
was attributed to a nameless “Citoyen de Genève.” See:
OC III.1.
Julie
, the “Letters of Two Lovers Who Live in a Small Town at the Foot of the Alps,” was
described as being “Collected and Published by Jean-Jacques Rousseau.” OC II.3. In the
Second
Preface
to
Julie
, Rousseau writes that he omitted the designation of his Genevan citizenship to “not
profane the name of my fatherland; I only put it on writings I believe will do it honor.” CW VI.20; OC
II.27.
623
Rousseau was concerned that the book would not be set in type in a timely fashion. As Cranston
describes, “Rousseau suggested there were only two ways to thwart the pirates [from printing
unauthorized copies], secrecy and diligence; and since there was no longer any secrecy about
Emile
,
diligence was all the more necessary.” This supports the contention that people knew of
Emile
(and
who its author was) long before it went to press. See: Cranston,
The Noble Savage
, pp. 300-301.
189
counting upon my uprightness and my innocence in this whole
business, and only too happy, whatever persecution was to await me,
to be called to the honor of suffering for the truth. Far from being
afraid and keeping myself hidden, every day I went to the Chateau and
in the afternoons I took my usual walk.
624
Rather than face facts, he “was tempted to believe that the entire world had gone
mad.”
625
He attributes this to his certainty of vaguely defined conspiracy theories, a
naïve faith in his own innocence, and a stubbornness to resist submission to the will
of his persecutors. He retired to bed with his “usual reading at night”
626
—the Bible—
and finished the
Book of Judges
, 19. It was then (at two in the morning) that his wife
Therese and M. la Roche entered with a letter on behalf on Mme. le Maréchal
627
from
M. le Prince de Conti. “The fermentation,” Rousseau recalls the letter as having said,
“is extreme; nothing can ward off the blow, the Court demands it, Parlement wishes
it; at seven o’clock in the morning a warrant will be issued for his [Rousseau’s] arrest,
and they will send to arrest him on the spot; I have obtained assurances that they will
not pursue him if he gets away; but if he persists in wanting to let himself be arrested,
he will be arrested.”
628
After a brief conference with le Maréchal, Rousseau concluded that it was
time to skip town. “I did not feel that I had either enough presence of mind, or
enough skill, or perhaps enough firmness to avoid compromising her if I was sharply
pressed. That made me decide to sacrifice my glory to her tranquility, to do for her
624
The Confessions
. CW V.485;OC I.579.
625
The Confessions
. CW V.485;OC I.579.
626
In light of the charges (of impiety), the more suspicious amongst us might view this claim as
pandering. Regardless, Rousseau notably portrays himself as a pious Christian whose bedtime routine
involved Bible study.
627
Mme. le Maréchal was a benefactor of Rousseau’s in Montmorency whom he describes earlier in
The Confessions
as “a lovable and powerful woman, to whom, in truth, I was becoming more attached
day by day.” CW V.446; OC I.532.
628
The Confessions
. CW V.485;OC I.580. For the correspondence to which Rousseau refers, see: CC
XI.1843.
190
on this occasion what nothing would have made me do for myself.”
629
The claim is
passive, stubborn, and sacrificial. Rousseau leaves Montmorency to assuage the
anxiety of his female friend. He follows his heart against his reasoned judgment,
foregoing personal “glory” to calm his companion’s fears. Regardless of his
retrospective reluctance, Rousseau’s flight was a harbinger of his life to come.
Outlawed from Paris to Geneva, the publication of
Emile
set in motion Rousseau’s
transformation from self-styled hermit to criminalized outcast.
630
Rousseau’s resistance to retreat may still strike an odd chord. Had he not
spent a career reiterating the practical, political and moral benefits of solitude? Yet
even in his earlier embrace of reclusiveness, he never completely abandoned society.
As
Emile
made plain, literal solitude was the fate of God, not man; the pupil’s
seclusion was a prelude to the involvement so central to Rousseau’s concept of civic
duty.
The Parlement’s arrest warrant changed everything. No longer granted the
luxury of peripheral asylum, Jean-Jacques was now an outcast. Hounded from
Môtiers to Bern, denounced by dear Geneva, he wandered in search of a homeland
while decrying his fate. During this “not all unwarranted” paranoia characteristic of
Rousseau’s waning years, Maurice Cranston argues, he “came to see himself as a
social outcast and concentrated on writing autobiographical works aimed at revealing
his essential innocence and truthfulness.”
631
He was indeed consumed with his own
acquittal. His ensuing works—from the
Letter to Beaumont
and
Letters Written From
629
The Confessions
. CW V.486;OC I.580-581.
630
Following this conversion of sorts, Jean-Jacques’ subsequent writings reflect an impassioned need
for acquittal. From
The Confessions
and
Dialogues
to the final
Reveries
, these later works bear the
distinct burden of an author in search of redemption, either in the public’s or God’s eye.
631
Cranston,
The Solitary Self
, p. xii.
191
a Mountain
to the
Dialogues
and
Reveries
—were written with an eye for redemption,
proffering numerous rejoinders to the grave injustice of his all-too-public persecution.
As an exile, Jean-Jacques felt compelled not only to defend himself but to
confront the consequences of his now-literal solitude. Where his retreat had earlier
served demonstrative and pedagogical purposes, he now approached reclusiveness as
an intensely personal matter. This development is most evident in his final work,
The
Reveries of the Solitary Walker
. Rousseau begins his swansong by stressing its self-
involvement, admitting (to whom, it is unclear) that “[t]here will be much concerning
me in them, because a solitary person who reflects is necessarily greatly preoccupied
with himself.”
632
Whereas Montaigne “wrote his
Essays
only for others,” Rousseau
wrote “only for myself.”
633
Taking self-examination as an enterprise in self-
edification, his work’s overarching concern was not society’s progress but its author’s
individual growth: “I will be happy if… I learn to leave life not better, for that is not
possible,” he confesses, “but more virtuous than I entered it.”
634
Crazier things have happened. After all, his entrance into the world was
dubious at best. “Cast from childhood into the whirlwind of the world,” Rousseau
confides, “I soon learned from experience that I was not made to live in it and that in
632
Reveries
(First Promenade). CW VIII.7; OC I.1000.
633
Reveries
(First Promenade). CW VIII.8; OC I.1001. Rousseau’s charge is somewhat misleading.
In his prefatory note “To the Reader,” Montaigne writes: “This book was written in good faith, reader.
It warns you from the outset that in it I have set myself no goal but a domestic and private one. I have
had no thought of serving either you or my own glory. My powers are inadequate for such a purpose.
I have dedicated it to the private convenience of my relatives and friends.” This is not, as Rousseau
suggests, the “complete opposite” of writing only for oneself. Furthermore, Montaigne’s work pursues
self-knowledge through measured self-examination, the same “goal” (and methodology) that Rousseau
sets for his
Reveries
: “to make myself aware of the modifications of my soul and of their sequence.”
Reveries
(First Promenade). CW VIII.7; OC I.1000. See also: Montaigne,
The Complete Essays
, p. 2.
634
Reveries
. (Third Promenade). CW VIII.27; OC I.1023.
192
it I would never reach the state my heart felt a need for.”
635
His life was plagued with
adversity, the pernicious twist of fate personalized as “undoubtedly a great teacher…
[that nonetheless] charges dearly for its lessons.”
636
Unfortunately, Rousseau was a
slow pupil. “What benefits do I get from such late and painfully acquired
enlightenment concerning my fate and concerning other people’s passions,” he asks
during the
Third Walk
? “By coming to know men better, I have only felt better the
misery into which they have thrust me; and while this knowledge has shown me all
their snares, it has not enabled me to avoid any.”
637
By the
Fifth Walk
, however, Jean-Jacques sings a slightly different tune. In
reflecting upon his life’s experiences, he gleans not sadness but solace. “I regret
these experiences in no way,” he now concludes, “since through reflection they have
given me new insights into knowledge of myself and into the true motives for my
conduct in a thousand circumstances I have so often deluded myself about.”
638
For
the beleaguered solitaire, life was a grueling test characterized by “years of
agitation”
639
which, in reflection, yielded retrospective clarity and eventual calm in
the face of adversity.
640
Rousseau’s ruminations still lead him towards a lonely conclusion: “of all the
studies I have tried to undertake during my life in the midst of men, there is hardly
635
Reveries
. (Second Promenade). CW VIII.18; OC I.1012.
636
Reveries
. (Third Promenade). CW VIII.17; OC I.1011.
637
Reveries
. (Third Promenade). CW VIII.17; OC I.1011.
638
Reveries
. (Sixth Promenade). CW VIII.51; OC I.1052.
639
Reveries
. (Third Promenade). CW VIII.24; OC I.1019.
640
Rousseau’s position here begs a comparison with Seneca. Following his exile from Rome, Seneca
approached his banishment as a period of “retirement.” He used this opportunity for reflection to
compose his
Epistulae Morales
, a work in which solitude is a catalyst for self-appraisal and measured
self-growth. I discuss Rousseau’s awkward relationship with Stoicism—his self-proclaimed affinity
and his decidedly un-Stoic behavior—in greater length elsewhere.
193
any I could not just as well have undertaken alone on a desert island.”
641
Far from
facilitating his desire to engage with the world, his antagonists seemed to thwart him
at every turn. “The greatest care of those who rule my fate having been to make
everything appear only false and deceptive to me, an occasion for virtue is never
anything but a lure they hold to draw me into the snare they want to enlace me in.”
642
The maliciousness of his nameless enemies weighs heavily upon his memories.
Apparently resigned to being at their mercy and convinced that he cannot act
independent of their influence, he retreats to a familiar refrain: “I know that the only
good which might henceforth be within my power is to abstain from acting, from fear
of doing evil without wanting to and without knowing it.”
643
Presented as an epiphany of sorts, the sentiment was nothing new. His pledge
of abstention harkened back to the “golden rule” of the
Second Discourse
.
644
Invoking the exile’s duty first described in
Emile
—“to bear the yoke of necessity
without complaining”—he again embraces inactivity and withdrawal as the key to his
liberation. Could such passive resistance free him from the yoke of his antagonists?
Only if Rousseau’s heart submitted to his mind; only if his reasoned conclusion
regarding the chimerical folly of virtue could quell his desire to seek virtue. In
Rousseau’s writings, Starobinski observes, “[t]he reflective man knows how to
641
Reveries
(Third Promenade). CW VIII.18; OC I.1013. Readers might here recall Rousseau’s
fascination with
Robinson Crusoe
, although even Crusoe had Friday by his side. As the first book
Emile is given to read see:
Emile
. E 184; OC IV.454-455.
642
Reveries
(Sixth Promenade). CW VIII.50; OC I.1051. Although the tone of this statement is
unabashedly paranoid (and borderline deranged), its substance is consistent with statements from
Rousseau’s earlier works on the safety and relative virtue of inactivity.
643
Reveries
. (Sixth Promenade). CW VIII.50; OC I.1051.. Because Rousseau maintains the innocence
of the human heart, he is accurately identified with Pelagianism. Yet he greatly mistrusts his active
will when swayed by social or societal pressures. If such “artificial” forces so frequently manipulate
and distort his “naturally” good will, does this render his affirmation of natural goodness moot? Put
another way, might Rousseau’s mistrust of activity reflect a more orthodox vision of humankind’s
sinfulness than his Pelagianism suggests?
644
Second Discourse
. CW III.38; OC III.156.
194
govern the mind of the sensuous man.”
645
Just as Wolmar guides Saint Preux and the
Tutor controls Emile, so did Rousseau (the exile-in-reflection) now call upon Jean-
Jacques (the sensual dreamer) to submit.
If action had indeed become futile and vaguely self-incriminating, Rousseau
presented himself two alternatives: to await salvation at the hands of divine
Providence, or abandon himself to his transcendent reveries. Although he began his
Confessions
invoking his day of reckoning (“Let the trumpet of the last judgment
sound when it will; I shall come with this book in my hands to present myself before
the Sovereign Judge”),
646
his
Reveries
turned with equal eagerness to flights of
imaginative fancy. The Island of Saint-Pierre became, through recollection, an
earthly heaven which sparked in him “[t]he sentiment of existence, stripped of any
other emotion… a precious sentiment of contentment and of peace which alone would
suffice to make this existence dear and sweet to anyone able to spurn all the sensual
and earthly impressions which incessantly come to distract us from it and to trouble
its sweetness here-below.”
647
Retreating from the frustrations of his physical life,
Rousseau once again found solace in nature and dream.
Although he recognized God’s hand in his own misfortunes—troubles too
swiftly orchestrated and coherently executed to be rooted in mere human will or non-
determinate chance—he did “not go so far as St. Augustine who would have consoled
himself to be damned if such had been the will of God.”
648
Indeed, his deferential
praise of God (the only true judge of innocence who alone is “the cause of my
645
Starobinski, 215
646
The Confessions
. CW V.5; OC I.5.
647
Reveries
(Fifth Promenade). CW VIII.46; OC I.1047. Reverie elevates Rousseau to a transcendent,
divine-like state: “As long as this state lasts, we are sufficient unto ourselves, like God.”
648
Reveries
. (Second Promenade). CW VIII.16; OC I.1010.
195
confidence”)
649
rings somewhat hollow. Rousseau did not, after all, rebuke his
earthly deeds as unpardonable sins. Quite the opposite, he stubbornly clung to his
own experiences as the simultaneous evidence of his goodness (he lived honestly and
truthfully) and source of his misery (others vengefully disagreed). Although acting
with integrity, speaking his mind, and trusting his friends furthered the severity of his
downfall, these experiences were without disgrace and even worthy of praise.
Kierkegaard understandably saw in this claim a notable dearth of Christian
humility: “What he lacks is the ideal, the Christian ideal, to humble him and teach
him how little he suffers compared with the saints, and to sustain his efforts by
preventing him from falling into the reverie and sloth of the poet.” Far from a martyr,
Rousseau simply “shows us how hard it is for a man to die to the world.”
650
Despite
asserting that self-examination has taught him the ability to accept hardship with
Stoic (or even Cynic) aplomb, Rousseau suffered horribly. More specifically, he
suffered as a man convinced of his innocence, not as a Christian who accepted his
ontological guilt. He assumed his worthiness in the eyes of God, while deflecting
culpability to those who controlled his corporeal fate.
Where men have failed Rousseau, the Lord will redeem him; of this he is sure.
“God is just,” he concludes; “He wills that I suffer; and He knows that I am innocent.
That is the cause of my confidence.”
651
But, as Kierkegaard reminds, who amongst
us is innocent? Augustine spent every waking minute of a far more pious life
affirming his own culpability. Maintaining faith is a grueling struggle for a man—
649
Reveries
. (Second Promenade). CW VIII.16; OC I.1010.
650
Søren Kierkegaard,
Journals
(4: 252-253), as quoted in Starobinski, p. 384 n. 23. For additional
discussion of Kierkegaard and Rousseau, see: Miller,
Rousseau: Dreamer of Democracy
, p. 190;
Grimsley,
Rousseau and the Religious Quest
.
651
Reveries
(Second Promenade). CW VIII.16; OC I.1010.
196
even a Saint—painfully aware that his very nature is tainted by sin. Yet for
Rousseau, “serene in my innocence,”
652
Divine contemplation offered detached peace
of mind. “Let me, therefore, leave men and fate to go their ways. Let me learn to
suffer without a murmur,” he concluded. “In the end, everything must return to order,
and my turn will come sooner or later.”
653
He was without blame, society guilty. In
confidently casting this stone, what was there to fear from One who surely grasped
this truth?
Rather than dreading his “turn,” Rousseau awaited divine judgment as a
framed man anticipates a noble trial. Cherishing the inevitability of his redemption,
he found one final companion in God—the only Being left who understood him. In
the end, Rousseau the recluse still sought solace
in another
, a final grasp that
illuminates the extent of his all-to-human attachment to attachment. Intoxicated by
the comfort of his own reveries, certain that he had “never been truly suited for civil
society,” convinced that “everything contributed to detach my affections from this
world, even before the misfortunes which were destined to alienate me from it
completely,” he seemed poised in the
Reveries
to finally retreat in peace.
654
Still, one cannot help but sense that perhaps as he did with Emile (nature’s
child pushed back into society), Rousseau had again set himself up to fail. His feet
straddled too many islands: a love of man and a mistrust of men, faith in political
reform and fear of hegemonic coercion, civic duty and social aversion, Cynic
shamelessness and Christian faith. Was the solitude born of these tensions
compelling, much less coherent? Did his recourse to reclusiveness illustrate the
652
Reveries
(Third Promenade). CW VIII.22; OC I.1019.
653
Reveries
(Second Promenade). CW VIII.16; OC I.1010.
654
Reveries
(Sixth Promenade). CW VIII.56; OC I.1059.
197
political and moral value of retreat? Did his appropriation of both spiritual and
secular tropes coalesce into something practicable, or did his model of retreat collapse
under the weight of its own conflicting concerns?
The temptation, as often befalls those confronting Rousseau, is to say that he
failed—that his theory was too fraught with contradictions, his character too weak to
realize the strength of his vision. But if we take him both as he was
and
as he wished
to be, perhaps we may still redeem him in the end.
For Rousseau, retreat provided a necessary means of enacting a noble plan, of
resisting societal corruption and girding oneself for the strenuous task of reform.
Return was its necessary correlative, the final, unavoidable test of applying lessons
learned in seclusion from the world to which we are inescapably bound. Only when
Rousseau was fiercely unwelcome did he supposedly abandon his earthly ties, tilting
his delicate balance by placing faith wholly in God and retreating into the solipsistic
daydreams of a defeated, isolated man.
Still, it took Rousseau until the year of his death to convince himself that he
had abandoned all hope. At that late stage, his acquiescence seemed terribly forced
and somewhat suspect. If we survey the evidence of his life and thought we might
instead conclude that Rousseau was never able to fully retreat, even when he had little
choice. What Kierkegaard identified as a lack of humility might therefore be
appraised as a deep-seated fear of abandonment—of relinquishing his civic duty and
leaving his peers to stumble towards a very suspect fate. To be sure, Rousseau
affirmed the virtues of passivity and inactivity, surrendering himself to nature,
198
reverie, and the forces that conspired against him. Yet he did so, Starobinski notes,
“with such energy as to belie the passivity in which he sought refuge.”
655
In 1762, Frederick the Great had this to say of the man to whom he granted
asylum in Neuchâtel:
I believe Rousseau missed his calling. He clearly had what it takes to
become a famous hermit, a Desert Father impressive because of his
moral rigor and his self-castigation, or a stylite. He would have
performed miracles, would have been canonized, and would have
increased the catalogue of martyrs even more. Nowadays, however,
he is seen only as a philosophical eccentric who tries to revive the sect
of Diogenes after two millennia. It does not pay to eat grass and make
enemies of all contemporary philosophers.
656
By this analysis, it was Rousseau’s involvement—not his solitude—that ushered his
downfall. Had he simply possessed the courage to abandon himself to an elusive
ideal he might have achieved the glory of martyrdom. But as history proves, he could
not stomach the severity of either Cynicism or Sainthood. Unlike Antony, he soiled
his hands in the affairs of men and never fully transcended their influence. And
unlike Diogenes, his outrage was a conceit adopted to mask the deep sensitivity of his
soul. Rather than embrace either model wholly, Rousseau straddled the line. His life
as a recluse was both demonstrative and resigned, righteous and profane. He found in
solitude a value that only God possessed, and urged it upon a corrupt, congested
world. He retreated—from Geneva, from Paris, from his peers, within himself—to
rekindle the divinely-scribed goodness lodged deep within his heart. Yet in
attempting to follow his conscience, he was freighted by the ever-present weight of
social pressures and earthly concerns.
655
Starobinski, p. 248.
656
Taken from Frederick the Great’s letter to the Governor of Neuchâtel, Lord George Keith, in
support of granting Rousseau asylum. Support notwithstanding, Frederick obviously took this
opportunity to air his grievances against Jean-Jacques. Quoted in: Niehues-Pröbsting, 344-345.
199
Rousseau might only have heeded Frederick’s advice to adverse
consequences. After all, the uniqueness of his vision lay in its amalgamation, its
stubborn mix of heuristic idealism and pessimistic realism, spiritual transcendence
and political virtue, piety and profanity. There is something both humble and brash in
a solitary thinker who nurtured both a Christian preoccupation with redemption and a
Pagan emphasis on corporeal achievement. Yet as he writes in
The Confessions
, “I
wished to live in independence but still needed to survive.”
657
Honest to the end, this,
finally, is the lesson of Rousseau: dreamer and recluse certainly, but one very much
involved with the society he never fully abandoned.
657
The Confessions
. OC I.363; CW V.304.
200
Chapter 5: Church and State
…the true disciples of Christ must suffer persecution; but that the church of Christ
should persecute others, and force others by fire and sword to embrace her faith and
doctrine, I could never yet find in any of the books of the New Testament.
—Locke,
A Letter Concerning Toleration
658
Now that there is no longer and can never again be an exclusive national Religion,
one should tolerate all those religions that tolerate others insofar as their dogmas are
in no way contrary to the duties of the Citizen. But whoever dares to say
there is no
Salvation outside of the Church
should be chased out of the State…
—Rousseau,
The Social Contract
659
Had Rousseau abandoned his concern with either spiritual welfare or secular
reform, he would not have struggled to envision a model of religious practice
compatible with democratic values of liberty, equality and tolerance. He would not,
in other words, have conceived of a Civil Religion. In
Letters Written from the
Mountain
, Rousseau describes this chapter of his
Social Contract
as “researches on
the manner in which Religion can and ought to enter as a constitutive part into the
composition of the body politic.”
660
The
Contract
’s most controversial section,
661
his
effort to transform religious associations was met with immediate, unmitigated scorn
by the Genevan Council.
662
Over two centuries later, criticism persists. Henri Gaston
Gouhier interpreted
Civil Religion
as an unabashed argument for total secularization
658
John Locke,
A Letter Concerning Toleration
(Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 1990), p. 25.
659
The Social Contract
. CW IV.223-224; OC III.469.
660
Letters Written From the Mountain
(Sixth Letter). CW IX.233; OC III.809.
661
Readers should consult Robert Derathé’s summary in OC III.1498-1500.
662
Helena Rosenblatt,
Rousseau and Geneva: From the First Discourse to the Social Contract, 1749-
1762
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), p. 258. For Rousseau’s response see:
Letters
Written From the Mountain
.
201
of the state.
663
More common rejoinders—such as that of Ronald Ian Boss—portray
Rousseau’s model as a thinly veiled justification for religious coercion.
664
Alfred
Cobban notes that
Civil Religion
has greatly contributed to Jean-Jacques’ reputation
“as the apostle of tyranny and an enemy to liberty in the state.”
665
And Lester G.
Crocker is most blunt, arguing that the practical consequences of Rousseau’s civic
faith “can only be imagined from the worst excesses of the Terror, or Stalinism, or of
Chinese communism.”
666
It seems fitting that our paradoxical author should again draw so much ire.
Perhaps part of this backlash is attributable to his task (reconciling two oft-
conflicting, passionately-held belief systems) and personality (a controversial figure
no matter his subject). Yet in one crucial aspect, Rousseau rendered himself an easy
target: earnest or no, his intentions were subverted by a sub-par effort. Tersely
developed as the last substantive chapter in
The Social Contract
,
Civil Religion
seems
as conspicuously awkward a fit as the
Profession of Faith
did in
Emile
. Of meager
length and polemic in tone, his engagement with this spirited topic smacks of
afterthought and ambivalence.
667
On one hand, Rousseau appears to follow in the
footsteps of thinkers like Montesquieu,
668
espousing traditional republican beliefs in
religion as a necessary foundation of civic virtue. He also devotes a majority of the
663
Henri Gaston Gouhier,
Les méditations métaphysiques de Jean-Jacques Rousseau
(Paris: J. Vrin,
1970), p. 255.
664
See: Ronald Ian Boss, “Rousseau’s Civil Religion and the Meaning of Belief: An Answer to
Bayle’s Paradox,”
Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth-Century
, 84, 1971, p. 123-193.
665
Alfred Cobban,
Rousseau and the Modern State
(London: G. Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1934), p. 88.
666
Lester G. Crocker,
Jean-Jacques Rousseau
,
Volume II
(New York: Macmillan Publishers, 1963), p.
184.
667
As Derathé notes,
On Civil Religion
was not in the draft of
The Social Contract
(the so-called
Geneva Manuscript
) that Rousseau initially sent to his publisher Michel Rey in December, 1760. OC
III.1498. Only after one year, in a letter to Rey dated December 23, 1761, did Rousseau admit to
adding this controversial section. CC IX.346.
668
See: Montesquieu,
The Spirit of the Laws
, Anne M. Cohler, Basia Carolyn Miller and Harold
Samuel Stone, eds. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), Part V Books 24-25.
202
text to denouncing religious practice’s role within polities. Discussing three inclusive
strains of worship—interior, exterior, and ecclesiastical—he concludes that all fail to
cultivate a strong, unified social body. He insists upon the necessity of religious
tolerance, yet his “civil” alternative regulates faith with an iron fist, even proposing
the death penalty to non-compliers—a strong claim offered almost in passing, without
due justification.
669
Winston Churchill once quipped that politicians should be judged by the level
of animosity they arouse amongst their opponents.
670
If Rousseau were a politician
today, he might give Bill Clinton a run for his money. But he was a political theorist,
and must be judged on the value of his thought rather than the passion of his
detractors. Considering its overwhelmingly negative reception, we might wonder if
his glaringly brief chapter
On Civil Religion
possesses any value whatsoever. Why
approach this problematic text when its author provides us with other works relevant
to our subject? Because we are using Jean-Jacques as a lens through which to
examine the relationship between religion and politics, and because
Civil Religion
offers the Genevan’s most famously concise practical application of this subject, it
begs closer scrutiny.
A measure of caution is nonetheless needed. In light of the heightened
controversy we will proceed slowly, devoting considerable space to examining the
development of Rousseau’s argument along with his more notorious contentions.
Keeping an eye to
Civil Religion
’s internal coherence while locating its affinity with
(and context within) his broader
oeuvre
, we will then assess its merits as the
669
The Social Contract
. CW IV.223; OC III.468.
670
The full quote attributed to Churchill reads as follows: “I have always felt that a politician is to be
judged by the animosities he excites among his opponents.”
203
practical solution Rousseau envisioned. In the final analysis, how does his “purely
civil profession of faith” resolve the dialectic between secularism and spirituality?
Does it present a viable means of reconciling the relationship between religious and
political institutions? Or does it merely add flame to this still-burning fire?
* * * * *
Rousseau began his chapter “On Civil Religion” with historical conjecture:
“Men at first had no other Kings than Gods, nor any other government than
theocracy.”
671
Well before the period when “men could bring themselves to accept a
fellow man as a master and flatter themselves that this was a good arrangement,” they
looked to divine rulers for governance.
672
Religion therefore served an explicitly
political function from the outset of human history. Long before the idea of self-
rule—even that exercised by a monarch or prince—seemed feasible, the
contemplation of heavenly figures provided a source of normative authority.
As he had in the
Second Discourse
, Rousseau again argued that socialization
changed everything. Individuals formed loose congregations which (over time)
evolved into nations, and citizens began to worship common deities legitimized by
corporeal leaders. “By the sole fact that God was placed at the head of every political
society,” Rousseau notes, “it followed that there were as many Gods as there were
peoples.”
673
Subsequent homogenization and centralization of these divine
figureheads within territorial borders helped to define national identities, but it also
671
The Social Contract
. CW IV.216; OC III.460.
672
Compare with the Vicar’s similar observation in
Emile
. E 288-289.
673
The Social Contract
. CW IV.216; OC III.460.
204
enflamed national rivalries. Because “peoples foreign to each other and nearly
always enemies could not recognize the same master… [nor] obey the same leader,”
politico-theological differences became a source of conflict. “Thus,” Rousseau
argues, “national divisions resulted in polytheism, and beyond that in theological as
well as civil intolerance.”
674
Despite these antagonistic conditions, he insists that
religious wars were nonexistent in Pagan times. This is because “each State, having
its own cult as well as its Government, did not distinguish between its Gods and its
laws. Political war was also Theological.”
675
This was certainly true of the Greeks, who brashly appointed themselves
“natural Sovereigns” of foreign tribes. This claim of dominion followed a theological
assumption: barbarians fell under Greece’s political jurisdiction because both peoples
worshipped the same Pagan Gods (even if unwittingly so). Such rationale was also
held by the Romans, for whom political and religious conquest was inextricably
linked.
676
Rome was, however, an Empire whose vast geopolitical expansion enabled
the unprecedented spread of its deities. This phenomenon incurred a sort of
theological globalization: “the Romans, having spread their cult and their Gods along
with their empire, and having themselves often adopted the Gods of the vanquished
by granting legal status… to them all, the peoples of that vast empire gradually
674
In describing these prejudices as “synonymous,” Rousseau establishes a core contention of his
chapter
On Civil Religion
: religious and civil
liberty
(like religious and civil
intolerance
) are connected
values.
The Social Contract
. CW IV.216; OC III.460.
675
The Social Contract
. CW IV.216; OC III.460.
676
History confirms Rousseau’s analysis of the conflation between spiritual and secular authority. It
was during Rome’s territorial expansion that
jus gentium
and
jus naturale
were formally codified, a
political necessity to institute and regulate Roman Catholicism throughout a sweeping Empire, when
the Mosaic Decalogue no longer sufficed to bind colonizers to colonies.
205
[came] to have multitudes of Gods and of cults, which were approximately the same
everywhere.”
677
Ironically, the very conditions which facilitated the proliferation of Rome’s
religion also contributed to its diffusion. Because the burgeoning Empire was
logistically incapable of micro-managing worship in newly-acquired territories, its
pantheon’s authority eroded. Although Rome continued to export deities throughout
it colonies, the sheer scope of its expansion prohibited the strict imposition and
codification of Roman faith. Religious cults flourished in this absence of strong,
centralized religious authority. In practice, nations incorporated into the Empire’s
fold (that lay beyond their conqueror’s immediate grasp) continued to worship their
own Gods even, Rousseau observes, with Rome’s legal approbation.
The emergence of autonomous cults within the Empire’s territories marked a
catalyst for momentous change. Specifically, it ushered the separation between
church and state, a radical schism with decidedly deleterious consequences. “By
separating the theological system from the political system,” Rousseau laments, “this
brought about the end of the unity of the State.”
678
The divorce of religion from
politics struck at the very heart of Pagan civic cohesion, and left subjects with two
distinct, competing authorities. “It was under these circumstances,” Rousseau argues,
“that Jesus came to establish a spiritual kingdom on earth.”
679
Initially, Jesus and his
followers sought merely to practice their worship without persecution from the state.
Skeptical Pagan leaders sensed a graver danger, regarding the sect “as true rebels
who, beneath a hypocritical submissiveness, were only awaiting the moment to
677
The Social Contract
. CW IV.217; OC III.462.
678
The Social Contract
. CW IV.217; OC III.462.
679
The Social Contract
. CW IV.217; OC III.462.
206
become independent of the masters, and to usurp adroitly the authority they pretended
to respect out of weakness.”
680
Pagan fears were realized when, following Jesus’
cataclysmic death, “the humble Christians changed their language, and soon this
supposedly otherworldly kingdom was seen to become, under a visible leader, the
most violent despotism in this world.”
681
Rousseau’s sudden, sharp conclusion begs emphasis: the destructive
relationship between religion and politics began not with their integration but their
radical separation. To reiterate his argument, religious cults flourished as Rome’s
political and spiritual authority weakened. The most enduring and infectious amongst
these—Christianity—rejected the jurisdiction of secular governments in spiritual
affairs, and anointed Christ mankind’s unequivocal master. As the Christian
following increased so did its clergy’s political power extend, eventually ruling the
very corporeal dominion it had originally shunned. The once-hunted cult of “the
Way” became a prolific hunter: “[t]he spirit of Christianity has won over everything,”
Jean-Jacques observes, in spiritual and secular realms alike.
682
It was a victory not without cost. According to Rousseau, clerical dominance
of secular polities crippled civil society. The seeds of disunity planted during Rome’s
downfall had blossomed into governments divided by mutually conflicting loyalties
to God and monarch. Civil and spiritual authorities butted heads, as this “double
power has resulted in a perpetual conflict of jurisdiction that has made any good
polity impossible in christian States.”
683
Jurisdictional schizophrenia cultivated a
680
The Social Contract
. CW IV.217; OC III.462.
681
The Social Contract
. CW IV.217-218; OC III.462.
682
The Social Contract
. CW IV.218; OC III.462.
683
The Social Contract
. CW IV.218; OC III.462.
207
perpetual confusion under which “no people has ever been able to figure out whom it
was obligated to obey, the master or the priest.”
684
This was true even when master
was
priest. As Rousseau writes, the Kings
and Czars of England and Russia—rulers who had “established themselves as heads
of the Church”—were ultimately subordinate to ecclesiastical authority. Dual
allegiances to earthly and otherworldly interests rendered them impotent. Their
powers became more managerial than legislative: “They have acquired not so much
the right to change [the church] as the power to maintain it.”
685
As “ministers”
subordinate to papal precepts (rather than autonomous “masters” of their realms),
these leaders possessed neither the political nor moral authority to rule
or
reform the
Church.
Papal dominance therefore posed a real-world threat to secular rule, one that
Hobbes had identified a century prior. Like Rousseau he “saw the evil and the
remedy” of divided sovereignty and “dared to propose the reunification of the two
heads of the eagle, and the complete return to political unity, without which no State
or Government will ever be well constituted.”
686
Still, Hobbes’ monarchal solution
was ultimately impractical; he underestimated the Church’s influence upon a single
ruler, no matter how powerful. As Rousseau chided, he was a “Christian Author”
687
who “ought to have seen that the dominating spirit of Christianity was incompatible
with his system, and that the interest of the Priest would always be stronger than that
684
The Social Contract
. CW IV.218; OC III.462.
685
The Social Contract
. CW IV.218; OC III.463.
686
The Social Contract
. CW IV.218; OC III.463.
687
Despite Rousseau’s certainty, Hobbes’ religious beliefs were—and remain—a matter of significant
dispute. For a fine summary of the various arguments in recent scholarship see: Patricia Springborg,
“Hobbes on religion,” in
The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes
, Tom Sorell, ed. (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 346-347, 369 n. 1.
208
of the State.”
688
Hobbes should have known that his own solution failed to
realistically anticipate organized religion’s predatory instincts. Sword be damned,
689
the Leviathan’s rule would inevitably be subjugated by the power of the priests.
In all fairness, Rousseau’s dismissal obscures the thoughtfulness with which
Hobbes confronted the politico-theological problem. After all, half of his
Leviathan
is devoted to the subject of religion. In Chapter 43 he explicitly identifies the
competing pulls of secular and spiritual loyalties as the principal cause of civil
conflict: “The most frequent pretext of Sedition, and Civil War, in Christian
Commonwealths hath a long time proceeded from a difficulty, not yet sufficiently
resolved, of obeying at once, both God, and man, then when their commandments are
one contrary to the other.”
690
Hobbes had a ready answer, one that showed deference
to the divine will. In such instances “when a man receiveth two contrary commands,
and knows that one of them is God's, he ought to obey that, and not the other, though
it be the command even of his lawful sovereign (whether a Monarch, or a sovereign
Assembly,) or the command of his Father.”
691
688
In an author’s note, Rousseau offers a very concise explanation of the clergy’s uniquely potent
authority. Fused “into a body” by a “social compact” (centered around communion and
excommunication), priests cultivate a singular will. A “political masterpiece,” their covenant unites
adherents “from opposite ends of the earth” under one common authority. This strong civil unity
explains why the clergy “will always be master of [divided] peoples and Kings”: they, like the
hypothetical citizens bound by Rousseau’s civil faith, derive political strength from adhering to a
common, unified will.
The Social Contract
. CW IV.218n; OC III.463n.
689
Rousseau’s critique may sound hyperbolic, but he identifies a cogent problem with Hobbes’
formulation: namely, the fact that Hobbes’ source of regulative order—corporeal punishment, or “the
sword”—holds little sway for those solely concerned with the afterlife and divine redemption. See
note 44 below.
690
Hobbes,
Leviathan
, Ch. 43 [321], p. 402.
691
To support this claim Hobbes cites Matthew 10:28: “
Fear not those that kill the body, but cannot
kill the soul
.” For Hobbes, divine retribution merits far more fear than the sovereign’s wrath. As he
explains: “If the command [of the sovereign] be such as cannot be obeyed without being damned to
eternal death, then it were madness to obey it, and the counsel of our Saviour takes place.” Ibid., Ch.
43 [321], p. 403.
209
This solution to the “most frequent pretext” of civil strife is not as naïve as
Rousseau would have us believe. Hobbes immediately recognized that his emphasis
upon obedience raised a logistical difficulty: “men when they are commanded in the
name of God, know not in diverse Cases, whether the command be from God, or
whether he that commandeth, do but abuse God’s name for some private ends of his
own.”
692
Although more staid in tone, these concerns revealed a sentiment consistent
with Rousseau’s own mistrust of ecclesiasts. Just as “many false Prophets”
693
bolstered their own reputations amongst ancient Jews with “feigned Dreams, and
Visions,” Hobbes continued, “so there have been in all times in the Church of Christ,
false Teachers, that seek reputation with the people, by fantastical and false
Doctrines; that seek reputation (as is the nature of Ambition,) to govern them for their
private benefit.”
694
He, like Rousseau, was acutely aware of the dangers
manipulative, ambitious priests posed to a gullible flock.
This common mistrust notwithstanding, they diverged sharply on two major
theological points. First, Hobbes believed that “we are all guilty of disobedience to
God’s Law” both ontologically (as descendents of Adam) and individually (“by our
own transgressions”).
695
And second, in
De Cive
he argued that the right to interpret
692
Ibid., Ch. 43 [321], p. 403.
693
Rousseau directly levied this charge of “false prophecy” against Beaumont, evoking Moses in
support of his refutation of miracles. The passage to which Rousseau referred comes from the Old
Testament in
Deuteronomy
13.1-3: “If a prophet arises among you, or a dreamer of dreams, and gives
you a sign or a wonder, and the sign or wonder which he tells you comes to pass, and if he says, ‘Let
us hp after other gods,’ which you have not known, ‘and let us serve them,’ you shall not listen to the
words of that prophet or to that dreamer of dreams; for the Lord your God is testing you, to know
whether you love the Lord your God with all your heart and with all your soul.” See:
Letter to
Beaumont
. CW IX.70; OC IV.990.
694
Hobbes,
Leviathan
, Ch. 43 [321], p. 403.
695
Ibid., Ch. 43 [322], p. 403.
210
scripture—the basis of divine law—“belongs to individual
churches
.”
696
As he
explained, such a power falls beyond the jurisdiction of “civil authority” and must
“depend either on the judgment of individual citizens or an outside authority. But it
cannot depend on the judgment of individual citizens: that can be seen from the
inconveniences and absurdities it would give rise to.”
697
In sum, “it is the task of a
church
to settle disputes; and therefore it is for a
church
, not for individuals, to
interpret holy scripture.”
698
As a Genevan Protestant with Pelagian sympathies,
Rousseau must have abhorred both conclusions.
699
He viewed the relationship
between God and man as a strictly private matter. Furthermore, as we have already
seen, he championed mankind’s natural innocence and rejected the narrative of
Original Sin. Given these profound disagreements, Rousseau could hardly have
considered Hobbes an ally in the politico-theological debates.
The Genevan was born into a heritage that shunned Roman Catholic directives
as intrusions upon the individual liberty to worship, breaches of political jurisdiction,
and offenses to the lessons of the Gospel.
700
On a more intimate note, this inherited
anticlericalism was reinforced by personal experience.
701
No stranger to the
ecclesiasts’ wrath, Jean-Jacques understood all-too-well the dangerous repercussions
of openly defying orthodox precepts.
702
For such a widely-read public figure as he—
696
Hobbes,
De Cive
, p. 230.
697
Ibid., p. 230.
698
Ibid., p. 231. See also: p. 245.
699
As he wrote to Voltaire, “whatever the Sophist Hobbes might have been able to say on this, when a
man serves the State well, he does not owe an account to anyone of the matter in which he serves
God.”
Letter from Rousseau to Voltaire
, August 18, 1756. CW III.119; OC IV.1072.
700
See: Rosenblatt, pp. 259-260.
701
For a summary of Rousseau’s exile see Chapter Four above.
702
Rousseau’s lack of anonymity separated him from other authors who dared take controversial
stances on religion such as, most notably, Voltaire.
211
one who dared challenge the priest’s authority—the politico-theological question was
hardly academic.
On both general and personal levels, Rousseau was firmly convinced that the
Catholic Church had overstepped legitimate spiritual
and
secular bounds. They
abused their duties as a religious authority by dictating terms of material worship that
both assumed humankind’s intrinsic guilt and required rote (and hence unfeeling)
repetition of hollow catechisms. And they exploited their political influence,
purveying an agenda of particularist interests characterized by hegemonic intolerance
and persecution. Subjecting citizens to their narrow interpretations of religious duty,
positive law, and spiritual salvation alike, they subverted the very foundation of a
healthy polity: civic cohesion reflective of a general will and grounded in the
Gospel’s benevolent, harmonious spirit.
In criticizing orthodox Catholicism, Rousseau had not merely entered a
Scriptural debate. His charge denied the Church’s authority as a legitimate mediator
between man and God. Interior faith was a matter of individual conscience and
personal belief; any ruling body which intervened contradicted the very will of God.
If true faith was nourished in the heart, particular rites fell under the realm of public
jurisdiction; exterior worship was by contrast a matter (as he quipped in
Emile
) of
public policy.
703
Yet following the terms established in
The Social Contract
,
religious congregations (like any civic association) were legitimate only if they
reflected a truly general will.
704
By contrast, the unilateral dictates of papists
703
Rousseau here sides with the Vicar, who argued that “external worship, if it must be uniform for the
sake of good order… is purely a question of public policy.”
Emile
. E 296.
704
Furthermore, because God imbued us with an inherent sense of
pitié
and universal brotherhood, this
unifying aim is consistent with Rousseau’s understanding of adherence to the divine will.
212
cultivated a singular dogmatism which disserved both God and man. Correcting
these abuses posed practical and political challenges: disavowing the Church of its
sole authority in spiritual matters; and reforming public worship in accord with the
democratic tenets of tolerance and civic unity.
As we have already seen, Rousseau insisted upon the necessity and utility of
his thought. The pragmatic emphasis evident in his introduction to
Civil Religion
was
equally explicit in the
Geneva Manuscript
.
705
Rousseau began this earlier draft by
stating his objective: “to put the machine in running order.”
706
By “machine” he
meant the political institutions that necessarily order social life. As in the
Second
Discourse
, malfunction was a consequence of denaturization, a development that
created new needs which “bring us together in proportion as our passions divide
us.”
707
Although human beings are naturally innocent, socialization gave rise to
wickedness. As our wants grew to surpass our needs, the “cupidity” exemplified by
amour-propre
weakened man’s sense of collective welfare and interdependence.
708
The satiation of particularist desires undermined natural harmony, an intuitive
sentiment which served as “the first bonds of general society” and “the foundations
of… universal good will.”
709
Still, “the more we become enemies of our fellow
men”—the more we pursue personal gain at the expense of others—“the less we can
705
Although the sections I address (I.1 and I.2) of the
Geneva Manuscript
were deleted from
The
Social Contract
, certain passages from I.2 are appropriated in Rousseau’s final chapter
On Civil
Religion
.
706
Geneva Manuscript
. CW IV.76; OC III.281.
707
Rousseau’s influence upon Hegel is evident in his dialectical analysis: “Thus the same causes that
make us wicked also make us slaves and reduce us to servitude by depraving us.”
Geneva Manuscript
.
CW IV.76; OC III.282.
708
Geneva Manuscript
. CW IV.76; OC III.282.
709
Geneva Manuscript
. CW IV.76-77; OC III.282.
213
do without them.”
710
This was a dilemma whose redress required hard labor, yet
“universal goodwill” remained a “fruit everyone would like to reap without being
obliged to cultivate it.”
711
If effort was wanting, the need was undeniable. In society, a “new order of
things gives rise to a multitude of relationships lacking order, regulation, and
stability.”
712
To further complicate matters, Rousseau admits that “nature’s gentle
voice is no longer an infallible guide for us, nor is the independence we have received
from her a desirable state.”
713
Human beings are, for better or worse, social creatures.
In this deracinated state, we no longer follow (let alone discern) the guidance of our
God-given conscience. Mankind is also painfully oblivious: “the sublime concepts of
a God of the wise, the gentle laws of brotherhood He imposes upon us, the social
virtues of pure souls—which are the true cult He desires of us—will always escape
the multitude.”
714
This is because people are easily swayed. They are fed “senseless”
Gods who, far from upholding morality and social cohesion, would lead them to
“indulge in a thousand horrible, destructive passions… if Philosophy and laws did not
hold back the furies of fanaticism.”
715
710
Geneva Manuscript
. CW IV.76; OC III.282.
711
Geneva Manuscript
. CW IV.77; OC III.282.
712
Geneva Manuscript
. CW IV.77; OC III.282.
713
The remainder of this passage offered a sharp rejoinder to those (most famously Voltaire) who
depicted Rousseau as overly-romanticizing nature. Here, however, Jean-Jacques is a hard realist: “We
lost peace and innocence forever before we had appreciated their delights. Unfelt by the stupid men of
earliest times, lost to the enlightened man of later times, the happy life of the golden age was always a
state foreign to the human race, either because it went unrecognized when humans could have enjoyed
it or because it had been lost when humans could have known it.” His bluntly honest assessment
underscores the pragmatism that I argue is central to Rousseau’s formulation of Civil Religion.
Geneva Manuscript
. CW IV.77; OC III.283.
714
Geneva Manuscript
. CW IV.79; OC III.285.
715
Geneva Manuscript
. CW IV.79; OC III.285.
214
The problem, however, lies with sectarianism rather than religion.
716
“Ever
since particular instructions became necessary, each People has its own ideas which it
is taught are the only valid ones, and which lead to Carnage and murder more often
than to harmony and peace.”
717
Rousseau instead urged us to “set aside the sacred
precepts of the various Religions, whose abuse causes as many crimes as their use can
avoid, and give back to the Philosopher the examination of a question that the
Theologian has never dealt with except to the detriment of the human race.”
718
Although these lines were removed in
The Social Contract
, they strike an odd chord
coming from one so mistrustful of the
philosophes
. Rather than read this as a reversal
of Rousseau’s well-documented suspicions, we should recognize in his plea an
unflinching indictment of those charged with religion’s keeping. Forced to choose
(on society’s behalf) between priests and philosophers, he sides here with the latter.
719
Although this admission occurs only in passing (in a draft, at that), it underscores an
insistence consistent throughout Rousseau’s
oeuvre
: theologians have made a mess
of religious institutions, a grievous gaffe for which humankind has paid a dear price.
Clearly, those charged with safeguarding and promoting that “greatest good of
all” (positive religion) have failed men where they are most in need. As Rousseau
concludes,
716
Given Rousseau’s historical analysis of religious associations, readers might wonder if sectarianism
and religion are fundamentally inseparable. Yet unless we allow him this crucial distinction, we
cannot accept his “civil faith” as a practical alternative to despotic dogmatism.
717
Geneva Manuscript
. CW IV.80; OC III.286.
718
For additional examples of Rousseau’s anticlericalism in
The Social Contract
’s final version
(beyond his chapter
On Civil Religion
), see Book II, Chapters 6-7 and Book IV, Chapter 7.
Geneva
Manuscript
. CW IV.80; OC III.286.
719
Of course, Rousseau vacillates on this subject. In
Emile
, for example, he writes that “fanaticism,
although more deadly in its immediate effects than what is today called the philosophic spirit, is much
less so in its consequences.”
Emile
. E 312.
215
although there is no natural and general society among men, although
men become unhappy and wicked in becoming sociable, although the
laws of justice and equality mean nothing to those who live both in the
freedom of the state of nature and subject to the needs of the social
state, far from thinking that there is neither virtue nor happiness for us
and that heaven has abandoned us without resources to the deprivation
of the species, let us attempt to draw from the ill itself the remedy that
should cure it. Let us use new associations to correct, if possible, the
defect of the general association.
720
Seemingly awash in despair, Rousseau draws hope from his faith in natural human
innocence and divine beneficence. Despite overwhelming evidence to the contrary,
God has not abandoned His worthy creations.
721
Rather than meekly suffer an
inalterable fate, we must summon courage and employ that most human of traits
722
—
perfectibility—to reform the “particular institutions” as necessary to human religion
as governments are to socialized man.
Writing on politics, education and social relations, Rousseau used starkly
honest critique—what I have previously referred to as
pessimistic realism
—as a
catalyst for
heuristic idealism
.
723
His approach to the politico-theological problem
724
was no different. As with inequalities, religious intolerance was a byproduct of
socialization, a corruption of the natural harmony instilled in us as creatures of God.
The dominance of papists perverted the spirit of the gospel by dictating terms of
salvation inconsistent with divine mercy and natural goodness, just as the Catholic
church infected society by dividing citizens and sovereignty. As in the
Second
720
Geneva Manuscript
. CW IV.81-82; OC III.288.
721
Rousseau immediately notes that “the human race… alone ought to decide [in such matters of faith]
because the greatest good of all is the only passion it has.” In typically paradoxical fashion,
Rousseau’s pessimistic realism and ontological optimism are in simultaneous evidence.
Geneva
Manuscript
. CW IV.80; OC III.286.
722
In the
Second Discourse
, Rousseau argued that free will and perfectibility are uniquely human traits
(unlike
pitié
and self-preservation, which animals possess). See: CW III.26-27; OC III.141-143.
723
For a further discussion of these terms, see Chapter One above.
724
As defined earlier, I use this term to mean the consideration of religion as it relates to politics.
216
Discourse
, redressing these wrongs demanded drawing “from the ill itself the remedy
that should cure it”: creating new associations to replace those that have failed us in
politics, society, and religion alike. If positive religion is particularly adrift, and its
reform is essential to a polity’s well-being, the task of instituting a civil religion is
nothing short of imperative.
* * * * *
We might here recall that Rousseau begins
The Social Contract
in search of
“legitimate and reliable rule.”
725
His vision takes shape as strong citizenship guided
by the general will, a unified volition shared and exercised by all. Reconceptualizing
the relationship between religion and politics (a nexus of divided loyalties) is
necessary to enact such valid political reform. If citizens do not resolve this
debilitating tension, they will be left dazed and confused, ruled by “two powers, two
Sovereigns”
726
—that of Christ as defined by a hegemonic church, and that of the state
as putatively defined by a monarch.
In the
Second Discourse
, speculative genealogy laid the foundation for a
sociopolitical critique of inequality. As in this earlier work, Rousseau’s introduction
to
Civil Religion
served a similar purpose: identifying the source of a social problem
in need of political redress. In both cases, an examination of the past established the
context to better assess and correct present failings. We may here take a moment to
725
The Social Contract
. CW IV.131; OC III.351.
726
The Social Contract
. CW IV.218; OC III.463.
217
review Rousseau’s historical account of religion, as it defines the problems
theoretically solved by Civil Religion.
Although the relationship between religion and politics took the initial form of
a relatively benign polytheism (much like early societies were characterized as loose
congregations of cooperative individuals), it became a source of despotism amongst
human societies. In the
Second Discourse
, the invention of private property marked a
decisive turning point in the evolution of civil society. In
Civil Religion
, Rousseau
locates a similar world-changing moment in the history of spiritual worship: the
advent of theological intolerance between nation-states, and the subsequent export of
deities to vanquished territories. Rome’s overexpansion subverted this practice, as
fringe cults sprouted throughout the Empire’s territory. Amongst these, Christianity
proved most enduring, and divested spiritual faith of its need for political affirmation.
More strongly, Christians opposed an Empire’s authority, drawing legitimacy from
faith in a single omnipotent divinity, and creating an autonomous ruling body who
answered to Christ above the Emperor. What began as a movement opposed to
earthly involvement eventually grew to dominate corporeal affairs.
In addition to providing a conceptual and historical foundation for his
argument, Rousseau’s introduction establishes three main concerns. First, theological
and civil intolerance—prejudices he describes as synonymous
727
—are products of
human history, unnatural to the extent that (like inequalities) they develop with
socialization and are nonexistent in the natural state. Second, politics and religion
were intimately linked from the first seedlings of human society. This relationship
was initially mutually beneficial, as divine rule served a normative, legislative,
727
The Social Contract
. CW IV.216; OC III.460.
218
unifying political function. Third, this balance was fundamentally (and permanently)
altered by Christianity, a faith that supplanted nationally-sponsored deities with a
universal God whose authority was autonomous from (and far more powerful than)
the state. This schism between religious and secular authority in turn created a
political problem, the phenomenon of sovereignty divided amongst monarchs and
priests. As Rousseau observes, the “sacred cult has always remained, or again
become independent of the Sovereign, and without a necessary bond with the body of
the State.”
728
It was this “necessary bond” that he sought to repair.
Before developing his solution, Rousseau quickly distances himself from the
fray of contemporary theological debate. Describing the two dominant poles of
thought epitomized by “the opposing sentiments of Bayle and Warburton, one of
whom claims that no Religion is useful to the body politic, the other of whom
maintains, to the contrary, that Christianity is its firmest support,”
729
he makes clear
his distaste for such arguments. Rousseau’s overriding aim is to re-forge religion’s
civic ties and reunite civil and religious faith, thereby imbuing strong democratic self-
rule with religion’s unifying moral foundation. He dismisses
chic
theological and
728
Rousseau’s comments on Islam underscore the tolerance he grants non-Christian faiths:
“Mohammed had very sound views; he tied his political system together well, and as long as the form
of the Government subsisted under his successors the Caliphs, the Government was completely
unified, and good for that reason. But when the Arabs became prosperous, lettered, polished, soft, and
weak, they were subjugated by barbarians. Then the division between the two powers began again…
[although] it is less apparent among the mohammedans than among the Christians.” Under this
assessment, corporeal prosperity—and not beliefs intrinsic to the Islamic faith—injured Arabic civil
unity; if anything, Christianity is more prone to divided sovereignty. This directly refutes
Montesquieu’s conclusion that “moderate government is better suited to the Christian religion, and
despotic government to Mohammedanism,” and offers a rejoinder to Locke’s proscription of the
“Mahometan” as one who could not live in political harmony with Christians. See: Montesquieu,
The
Spirit of the Laws
, p. 461; Locke,
A Letter Concerning Toleration
, pp. 63-64;
The Social Contract
.
CW IV.218; OC III.462-463.
729
The Social Contract
. CW IV.219; OC III.463-464.
219
philosophical arguments as fundamentally irrelevant to his study, one guided by
practical—not metaphysical—concerns.
Rousseau’s aversion to theological debates reflects an even deeper conviction.
As we saw in Chapter 3, he believed divine mysteries were ultimately impenetrable.
Humankind was capable of discerning only the most general characteristics of God
(omnipotence and beneficence) and His will (exemplified in the order of the natural
world). Beyond these vague certainties, theological speculation was wholly
indeterminate. Efforts to apply particular characteristics to a Being beyond human
comprehension were vain in both senses of the word: ineffectual and unduly proud.
Rather than attempt to settle questions irresolvable to the human mind,
730
Rousseau
strove only to “give a little more precision to the overly vague ideas about Religion
that are relevant to my subject.”
731
Before developing his subject—a “purely civil profession of faith”—Rousseau
begins with a typology, dividing religion “into two types, namely the Religion of man
and that of the Citizen.”
732
The first “is the pure and simple Religion of the Gospel…
and what may be called natural divine right,” an
internal
worship “without Temples,
altars, or rituals.”
733
The second is practiced by and within specific countries, an
external
worship of “dogma, rites, and external cult… prescribed by law.”
734
Rousseau adds a “third, more bizarre, type of Religion which, by giving men two
730
Note that Rousseau here sides with the Stoic critique of rhetoric recounted in Plutarch’s
Moralia
,
Volume XIII, Part II, and discussed in Chapter 2 above.
731
On the subject of clarity, although
religion
is (according to the
Oxford English Dictionary
) of
“doubtful etymology” writers after Cicero frequently attributed its origins to the term
religre
, “to
bind.” Rousseau draws upon this sense of legitimate constraint in claiming that a purely civil faith can
be regulated by a corporeal sovereign.
The Social Contract
. CW IV.219; OC III.464.
732
The Social Contract
. CW IV.219; OC III.464.
733
The Social Contract
. CW IV.219; OC III.464.
734
The Social Contract
. CW IV.219; OC III.464.
220
legislative systems, two leaders, and two fatherlands, subjects them to contradictory
duties, and prevents them from being simultaneously devout men and Citizens.”
735
He has in mind Roman Catholicism or “the religion of the Priest,” one that “leads to a
type of mixed and unsocial right that has no name.”
736
Rousseau immediately (and categorically) dismisses the “religion of the
Priest” as being “so manifestly bad that it is a waste of time to amuse oneself by
proving it.”
737
Catholicism fails to uphold the most basic requisites of the social
contract: it “destroys social unity” and “put[s] man in contradiction with himself,”
rendering it “worthless” and—given Rousseau’s concept of divine order—
fundamentally irreligious.
738
The remaining categories have more forgivable flaws.
External worship “combines the divine cult and love of the laws,” a union that
renders “the fatherland the object of the Citizens’ adoration.”
739
Such a formula
transforms the state into a “tutelary God,” a “kind of Theocracy in which there ought
to be no other pontiff than the Prince, nor other priests than the magistrates.”
740
If
Rousseau appreciated such patriotic
eros
, he remained mistrustful of unilateral
hierarchical authority. Like papists, theocrats conflated secular and spiritual
jurisdiction.
741
Furthermore, their muddled creed was “bad in that, being based on
error and falsehood, it deceives men, makes them credulous, superstitious, and
735
Readers should note Rousseau’s wholly dismissive numeration. By initially claiming that religion
can be “divided into two types,” he implies that Catholicism (a “third, more bizarre, type”) barely even
qualifies as a religion.
The Social Contract
. CW IV.219; OC III.464.
736
The Social Contract
. CW IV.219; OC III.464.
737
The Social Contract
. CW IV.219; OC III.464.
738
The Social Contract
. CW IV.219; OC III.464.
739
The Social Contract
. CW IV.219; OC III.464-465.
740
The Social Contract
. CW IV.220; OC III.465.
741
Furthermore, both Roman Catholicism and theocracy failed to coherently define (and subsequently
separate) these two distinct domains. As a Genevan, Helena Rosenblatt argues, Rousseau was
“particularly sensitive” to such matters. The experience of his
patrie
had illustrated the more
dangerous “political uses of religion and… political implications of certain beliefs. He was well aware
that some dogmas were being used by the authorities to depoliticize the people.” Rosenblatt, p. 261.
221
drowns the true cult of divinity in empty ceremonial.”
742
Under this system, the
gospel was supplanted by arbitrary ritual, cultivating a faith based upon credulity and
intolerance rather than the truth and harmony characteristic of God’s will.
Having examined the problems of state- and priest-based worship, Rousseau
returns to his first category: “the Religion of man, or Christianity,” which he
immediately distinguishes from “that of today.” The faith he envisions is a “saintly,
sublime, genuine Religion, [which urges] men—all children of the same God—[to]
acknowledge one another as brothers,” a bond which survives even death.
743
From
the perspective of civil society, the problem with Christianity is that it lacks any
“particular relation to the body politic, [and] leaves laws with only their intrinsic
force, without adding any other force to them.”
744
Rousseau here resurrected a
familiar critique of Christianity’s incompatibility with political action, describing
earthly indifference as a symptom of solely focusing upon the afterlife. As he
lamented, “far from attaching the Citizens’ hearts to the State, it detaches them from
it as from all worldly things,” a phenomenon completely “contrary to the social
spirit.”
745
Even more strongly, he argued that “a society of true christians would no
longer be a society of men.”
746
Such individuals would be wholly united with God
and wholly detached from their fellows.
This is because “Christianity is a totally spiritual religion, uniquely concerned
with Heavenly matters.”
747
Although true Christians are dutiful, law-abiding,
742
The Social Contract
. CW IV.220; OC III.465.
743
The Social Contract
. CW IV.220; OC III.465.
744
In so doing, Christian corporeal indifference weakens “one of [society’s] great bonds.”
The Social
Contract
. CW IV.220; OC III.465.
745
The Social Contract
. CW IV.220; OC III.465.
746
The Social Contract
. CW IV.220; OC III.465.
747
The Social Contract
. CW IV.220; OC III.466.
222
moderate, incorruptible, brave and temperate, “[t]he Christian’s fatherland is not of
this world.”
748
Civil duties would be performed “with profound indifference for the
good or bad outcomes of his efforts.”
749
Whatever his state’s fortunes may be, the
Christian either ignores its felicity or “blesses the hand of God that weighs heavily on
his people.”
750
He allows himself neither pride in his
patrie
, nor the will needed to
reform a polity in decline. As we have already seen, this mirrors a fundamental
division between Augustine and Pelagius. Augustine saw little hope in meaningful
human reform, save constant vigilance carried out with the realization that
redemption might only follow the grace of God. By contrast, Pelagius embraced
corporeal improvement as a means of actively soliciting the divine Creator’s mercy.
Arguing that salvation and earthly improvement were mutually constitutive aims,
Rousseau seemed to side with Pelagius.
If the Christian state denuded citizens of their capacity for physical self-
betterment, it possessed another fatal weakness. Such a polity could prosper only if
“all Citizens without exception… [were] equally good Christians.” This is because
those truly devoted to Christ are not simply indifferent to their corporeal fates; they
are also utterly naïve, awash in blind brotherly love that makes them easy victims for
even “a single ambitious man, a single hypocrite.”
751
Such ingenuousness combined
with a passive attribution of fate to the will of God do not strong citizens make.
748
The Social Contract
. CW IV.220; OC III.466.
749
The Social Contract
. CW IV.220; OC III.466.
750
The Social Contract
. CW IV.221; OC III.466.
751
If Rousseau’s fear appears to be at odds with his belief in man’s natural goodness, we must recall
that he hardly withheld from casting blame. Although
man
might be innocent by nature,
men
had
certainly made a mess of denatured society. As with Pelagius, his faith in natural goodness never
blinded him to the shortcomings of society. In this he (as an individual) differs sharply from the
Christian for whom “charity makes it hard to think ill of one’s neighbor.”
The Social Contract
. CW
IV.221; OC III.466.
223
Because the Christian’s “essential thing is to go to paradise,” they lack the worldly
devotion needed to cultivate or defend their States.
752
Christianity may nourish
deeper existential truths and worship a just deity, but—like natural man—its “true”
practitioners are ill-suited for society. As Rousseau concludes,
I am mistaken when I speak of a Christian Republic;
753
these two
words are mutually exclusive. Christianity preaches nothing but
servitude and dependence. Its spirit is so favorable to tyranny that
tyranny always profits from it. True Christians are made to be slaves.
They know it and are scarcely moved thereby; this brief life is of too
little worth in their view.
754
Passages such as these evoke thinkers from Machiavelli
755
to Nietzsche
756
who levied
stark critiques against the slavish disposition of Christian faith. As Machiavelli wrote
in the
Discourses on Livy
, “while our religion has shown us truth and the true path, it
also makes us place a lower value on worldly honor.”
757
In addition, Christianity
“has more often glorified humble and contemplative men rather than active ones,”
and “defined the supreme good as humility, abjection, and contempt of worldly
things.”
758
Just as Rousseau asserted that Christians neglect corporeal concerns in an
752
“Suppose that your christian republic is face to face with Sparta or Rome,” Rousseau wonders. The
results would not be pretty: “the pious christians will be beaten, crushed, destroyed before they have
had time to look around, or they will owe their salvation only to the scorn their enemies will conceive
for them.”
The Social Contract
. CW IV.221; OC III.466-467.
753
For a comparison with Locke’s similar assertion, see below.
754
The Social Contract
. CW IV.221; OC III.467.
755
The association is none too favorable. In the 1539
Apologia Reginaldi Poli ad Carolum V
,
Reginald Pole described Machiavelli’s works as “written by the finger of Satan,” a not uncommon
view amongst the more spirited detractors. It is nonetheless worth noting that, as with Rousseau, not
everyone saw the Devil as Machiavelli’s muse. In his massive 1668
Apologie pour Machiavel
(commissioned by Cardinal Richelieu), Louis Machon defended the
Discourses
and
The Prince
as
saintly efforts “drawn from the book of books” itself, the Holy Scripture. Peter S. Donaldson,
Machiavelli and the Mystery of State
(New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988), pp. xi, 9 & 188.
756
In addition to
Genealogy of Morals
I.11, readers should also consult I.7, I.13, II.7, as well as the
following:
Beyond Good and Evil
§62, 260;
The Will to Power
§8, 90;
The Antichrist
§571.
757
Machiavelli,
Discourses on Livy
, II.2 p. 158.
758
Ibid., II.2 p. 159.
224
effort “to go to paradise,” so did Machiavelli argue that “in order to go to paradise,
most men think more about enduring their pains than about avenging them.”
759
If Rousseau’s indictment of Christian citizens followed Machiavelli (at times
to the letter), it also resurrected Bayle’s depiction of Christian states as fundamentally
apolitical entities.
760
By reviving these controversial stances Rousseau seemed to
enter the very theological debates he had dismissed mere pages earlier. Such
apparent reversals make Civil Religion a particularly frustrating text, even by
Rousseau’s paradoxical standards. Yet what appears blatantly contradictory more
accurately alludes to a deep ambivalence. Rousseau insisted upon the necessity of
integrating religious practice within legitimate political associations. At the same
time, he recognized that organized religion historically opposed republican civic
interests: theocratic states were built upon lies and cultivated credulous intolerance;
and Catholic polities were dominated by dangerous dogmatists. Even “true”
Christians were ill-suited to the rigorous corporeal duties of strong citizenship.
Each form of religious practice categorically undermines the conditions
requisite of a prosperous civic body. None are capable of simultaneously preserving
religion’s most beneficial elements (truth, harmony, connectedness, moral will) and
the core values of legitimate polities (freedom, tolerance, unity). In all three
instances, spiritual associations seem fatally incompatible with political associations,
doomed either to dominate corporeal governance, supplant true faith with narrow-
minded superstition, or create a citizenry fatally disinterested in worldly affairs.
Before even sketching his alternative, Rousseau has planted a significant doubt: are
759
Ibid., II.2 p. 159.
760
Readers should refer to Pierre Bayle’s 1697
Dictionnaire historique et critique
. For a refutation of
Bayle see: Montesquieu,
The Spirit of the Laws
Part V, Book 23, Chapters 2 & 6.
225
religion and politics fundamentally incompatible, or can Civil Religion succeed
where all others have failed? In provoking such uncertainty, he prods readers to
question his very enterprise.
Because Rousseau seemed to portray religious associations as the proverbial
oil to a healthy polity’s water, it should come as no surprise that commentators have
read his chapter
On Civil Religion
as a wholly secular plea in spiritual clothing and
(more broadly) labeled its author emphatically irreligious. The evidence for such an
interpretation lies in plain view. Yet as I have argued throughout, such conclusions
dismiss a crucial element of Rousseau’s thought: his sincere religiosity. To ignore
this is to place him in the company of atheist
philosophes
such as Helvétius, Holbach
and d’Alembert whose views, he argued in
Emile
, were more dangerous than
fanaticism itself.
761
Religion fulfills a unique and fundamental role in the moral
composition and civic harmony of communities. That dogmatic creeds nullify this
value should compel rather than deter us to reform spiritual associations. An essential
facet of human life, like social bonds they
must
be repaired.
762
To justify this claim that Rousseau was a thinker equally committed to secular
and spiritual well-being, we must nonetheless resolve the doubts his condemnation of
Christianity rightfully raise. Rousseau’s critique of the Christian citizen is
problematic on at least three levels. First, it seems to render his very enterprise
(“considering [religion] in relation to society”) moot by placing religion in
fundamental opposition to society. Second, it seems self-subverting when considered
761
See:
Emile
. E 312.
762
Again, this position sharply separates Rousseau from his atheist
philosophe
peers.
226
in relation to Rousseau’s descriptions of himself as a “true” Christian.
763
Finally,
unlike his anticlericalism which attacks overtly (and actively) self-serving papists, it
targets a relatively benign group: the genuinely faithful. What then are we to make of
an argument to integrate religious practice into civil society that begins by dismissing
even the most exemplary practitioners?
By way of explanation, Helena Rosenblatt argues that these “provocative
statements… should not be taken at face value.”
764
Placing Rousseau’s chapter on
Civil Religion within the context of Genevan politics, she describes Rousseau’s
“strategy” as a method of “adopt[ing] and amplify[ing] the Genevan patriciate’s
version of Christianity, only to turn it against them.”
765
To secure their own political
power, the patriciate “claimed that Christianity preached only otherworldliness,
submission, and resignation.”
766
Rousseau simply took this conclusion to its logical
extreme, describing a “Christian republic” as a contradiction in terms.
767
According
to Rosenblatt, his position was deliberate, a means of “provoking people to defend
their religion and, in the process, to refute the patriciate’s ‘Christian submission’
763
For an assessment of Rousseau’s self-description as a “true Christian” see Chapter Six below,
where I discuss his religiosity through the lens of his “conversions” to both Catholicism (as a youth
under de Warens’ direction) and philosophy (on the road to Vincennes).
764
Rosenblatt, p. 263.
765
Rousseau himself substantiated this reading in a 1763 letter to Deluc: “The surest way to refute [the
Genevan patriciate’s] maxims is to force them to deduce the consequences of them themselves and to
take them as far as they will go.” From CC XVII.279-280, as quoted in Ibid., p. 263.
766
Ibid., pp. 263-264.
767
Locke similarly claimed that “there is absolutely no such thing… as a Christian commonwealth.”
His argument was rooted in a technical reading of the Gospel, in which he finds no evidence that a
commonwealth was ever “constituted upon that foundation” of Christian faith, or “in which God
himself was the legislator.” Lest we overemphasize their affinities, readers might also consult
Rousseau’s refutation of Lockean epistemology written in a 1755 letter to Voltaire: “The true
principles of optimism can be drawn neither from the properties of matter, nor from the mechanics of
the universe, but only by inference from the perfections of God who presides over everything.” Locke,
A Letter Concerning Toleration
, pp. 52-53.
Letter to Voltaire
(August 30, 1755). CW III.115; OC
IV.1068.
227
argument. Rousseau’s readers had to choose: either Christianity does not preach
submission, or its political relevance must be rejected.”
768
Because
Civil Religion
proceeds from the premise that religion is politically
relevant, Rosenblatt argues that its exaggerated anti-Christian stance must be read as
a negative lesson, a means of prodding readers to understand the dangers in
categorically dismissing Christianity’s political value. This was the very explanation
Genevan minister Antoine-Jacques Roustan offered in an amicable retort to his
friend’s hyperbolic position. In
O
f
rande aux Autels et à la Patrie
, Roustan wondered
aloud if “M. Rousseau believe[s what he has written] himself.”
769
After all,
Christianity requires good acts; it encourages self-sacrifice in the face of tyranny; and
it preaches submission only as a last resort.
Yet if these values were well-suited to republicanism, and “if Christianity is
so favorable to liberty, [why are there] so few free states in Europe?”
770
Roustan
provided a decidedly Rousseauist answer to this Rousseauist question: “because there
are so few Christians.”
771
As he continued, “an ambitious person… would have to
think twice before attacking the liberty of a really Christian people, whose citizens
would scorn riches, would lead a simple, laborious, frugal life, would love each other
like brothers and future fellow-citizens of heaven.”
772
This analysis tacitly suggests
that greed and covetousness (qualities Rousseau associated with the Genevan
patriciate), not humility and brotherly love, threaten strong citizenship. It also
768
Rosenblatt, p. 264.
769
Roustan was also instrumental in getting Rousseau’s
Social Contract
approved (by the censors) and
published. Antoine-Jacques Roustan,
Offrande aux Autels et à la Patrie
(Amsterdam: Michel Rey,
1764), as quoted in Ibid., p. 264.
770
Ibid., p. 265.
771
Readers should note that Diogenes the Cynic reached a similar conclusion when searching for a
“real man” in broad daylight while holding a lantern. See Chapter Four above.
772
Ibid., p. 265.
228
reiterates an argument familiar to Rousseau’s readers: religion
rightly understood
bears little in common with most contemporary religious practice.
Just as Papal abuses should not obscure true religion’s value to humankind,
Jean-Jacques’ anticlericalism should not be confused with irreligiosity. Indeed, his
vision of a legitimate society was grounded in a unified sense of duty or “moral will”
which, in turn, “was dependent upon the existence of God.”
773
Did these convictions
redeem him from charges of impiety? Rousseau certainly thought so. Revisiting
The
Social Contract
in the Third of his
Letters Written from the Mountain
, his writes:
One cannot say… that I attack morality in a Book in which I establish
with all my power the preference for the general good over the private
good and in which I relate our duties toward men to our duties toward
God; the only principle upon which morality can be founded, in order
to be real and go beyond appearance.
774
An obligation to serve God, fellow man, and the general good: these are the moral
precepts Rousseau draws from his belief in a divine universal order. And as the
“most reasonable and holy Religion on earth,” Christianity powerfully affirms these
duties.
775
Jean-Jacques was emphatic on this point. Flatly denying “that Christianity is
attacked in my [
Social Contract
],”
776
he described it as “a book where the truth,
utility, and necessity of Religion in general is established with the greatest force;
where, without making any exception, the Author prefers the Christian Religion to
773
Despite their shared skepticism, this position clearly distinguishes Rousseau from that of Bayle.
Rosenblatt, p. 265.
774
Letters Written from the Mountain
(Third Letter). CW IX.191; OC III.758.
775
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.47; OC IV.960.
776
Again, what he
did
attack were “the distinctive dogmas of the Catholics” quick to condemn man in
both this and the after-life. As Rousseau protested, “
to machinate
… is to do what certain people”—
namely, Roman Catholics—“do against Christianity and against me.”
Letters Written From the
Mountain
(Third Letter). CW IX.190; OC III.757.
229
any other worship and the evangelical Reformation to any other sect.”
777
Yet despite
this praise, Rousseau never retracted his more disparaging sentiments about the
“purely spiritual faith.” Clarifying his critical position, he argued that Christianity—
although “making men just, moderate, and friends of peace” and being “very
favorable to the general society”—“weakens the force of the political spring [and]
complicates the movements of the machine.”
778
Being “not sufficiently suited to
[corporeal politics]… it must either degenerate or remain a foreign and cumbersome
component.”
779
Although Christianity served human life and livelihood, it was still a
disembodied belief-system ill-equipped to impose the rigorous corporeal duties
essential to a strong polity’s welfare. Rousseau’s conclusion, borne of realistically
appraising the practical values and limits of different forms of religion, carved a sharp
distinction between interior and exterior worship. In the process, it also forced
readers to judge his project on its own explicitly social terms.
* * * * *
True religion neither divides nor oppresses humankind; it simply cultivates a
healthy deference to divine order. Yet as Rousseau illustrated, religious associations
rarely reinforced God’s harmonious will. In a 1755 letter to Voltaire, he blamed “the
Priests and the Devout” for this failing.
780
Rather than developing our moral sense by
777
It is worth noting that as evidence, Rousseau entreats readers (in an author’s note) to consult his
postscript to the Vicar’s
Profession
in
Emile
.
Letters Written From the Mountain
(Second Letter).
CW IX.159; OC III.718-719.
778
Letters Written From the Mountain
(First Letter). CW IX.148; OC III.705.
779
Letters Written From the Mountain
(First Letter). CW IX.148; OC III.705.
780
This was, of course, a typically Protestant stance that Rousseau here adopts.
230
preaching compliance with “the established order,” they “have Divine justice
intervene” only when it serves their dogmatic teachings.
781
They supplant the
fraternité
and
pitié
natural to God’s creations with fear of papal authority and
intolerance towards non-believers. And finally, because “it matters greatly to the
State that each Citizen have a Religion that causes him to love his [civic and moral]
duties,” they undermined the very requisites of healthy, virtuous polities.
782
Rousseau’s alternative to such a divisive dogmatism was Civil Religion, a
purely civic faith fettered only by “the limits of public utility.”
783
Beyond this
guiding principle, his formulation was purposefully broad.
784
So long as religious
worship did not conflict with society’s general interests, the specific tenets of the faith
were irrelevant:
the dogmas of that Religion are of no interest either to the State or to
its members; except insofar as these dogmas relate to morality, and to
the duties that anyone who professes it is obliged to fulfill toward
others. Everyone can have whatever opinions he pleases beyond that,
without the Sovereign having to know what they are. For since the
sovereign has no competence in the other world, whatever the fate of
subjects in the life hereafter, it is none of its business, as long as they
are good citizens.
785
A sharp line is carved in stone. The State has no business intruding upon personal
beliefs which do not compromise the general welfare of its citizens. Although our
relationship with God is a sacred and private source of individual moral strength,
religious associations must serve public interests and be held accountable to the same
civic standards applicable to any legitimate community.
781
Letter from Rousseau to Voltaire
, August 30, 1755. CW III.116; OC IV.1068-1069.
782
The Social Contract
. CW IV.222; OC III.468.
783
The Social Contract
. CW IV.222 OC III.467.
784
In this, Rousseau sides with the Vicar who argued that “particular dogmas” confuse and debase
“notions of the great Being… instead of establishing peace on earth, they bring sword and fire to it,”
making “man proud, intolerant, and cruel.”
Emile
. E 295.
785
The Social Contract
. CW IV.222; OC IV.468.
231
Because the articles of such a “purely civil profession of faith” are less
“Religious dogmas” than “sentiments of sociability without which it is impossible to
be a good Citizen or a faithful subject,” they must be established by the Sovereign.
786
Precepts essential to a polity’s moral health, they reflect only the most general,
universally accessible tenets of the Gospel. In this, Rousseau sides with his Vicar:
“The dogmas of the civil Religion ought to be simple, few in number, stated with
precision, without explanation or commentaries.”
787
Specifically, they require belief
in “[t]he existence of a powerful, intelligent, beneficent, foresighted, and providential
Divinity; the afterlife; the happiness of the just; the punishment of the wicked.”
788
Rousseau also adds a strict civil caveat to these core Christian assumptions: “the
sanctity of the social Contract and the Laws” must always be observed.
789
From the outset, Civil Religion shows simultaneous deference to both divine
and human order, vesting its authority in spiritual truths and secular precepts. Beliefs
in an omnipotent God and the afterlife, and a righteous heavenly order which rewards
justice and punishes wickedness are balanced by the inviolability of positive law
defined by the general will. To these “positive” stipulations, however, Rousseau adds
one crucial “negative” dogma: intolerance is proscribed.
790
A caveat essential to
upholding individual liberty, this final term reflects Jean-Jacques’ insistence that
intolerance fundamentally opposes spiritual and secular freedom.
786
Pierre Burgelin rightly notes the spiritual quality of this secular covenant, a pact between citizens
and sovereign that “must be called
sacred
.” This is because the social contract rests upon an act of
will
, what Rousseau described in the
Second Discourse
as a Cartesian ‘operation of the soul.’ As he
made clear, “in the sentiment of this power [of willing] are found
only purely spiritual acts
about
which the Laws of Mechanics explain nothing.” (My emphasis.)
Second Discourse
. CW III.26-27;
OC III.142-143. Pierre Burgelin,
Jean-Jacques Rousseau et la religion de Genève
, p. 32.
787
The Social Contract
. CW IV.223; OC III.468.
788
The Social Contract
. CW IV.223; OC III.468.
789
The Social Contract
. CW IV.223; OC III.468.
790
The Social Contract
. CW IV.223; OC III.468-469.
232
His negative dogma also reveals a deep mistrust of a creed like Catholicism
which “dares to say
there is no Salvation outside of the Church
.”
791
Such
presumptuous sects should, on no uncertain terms, “be chased out of the state.”
792
Their expulsion is merited by crimes against both civil and theological order:
claiming to monopolize the gift of salvation, ecclesiasts falsely usurp a power held
solely by God; and they sharply divide polities by condemning those outside their
flocks to Hell. This is certainly no way to build a congregation, much less a society.
As Rousseau notes, on a practical level “[i]t is impossible to live in peace with people
whom one believes are damned. To love them would be to hate God who punishes
them. They must absolutely be brought into the faith or tormented.”
793
A theological
stance with decidedly despotic corporeal consequences, the Catholic position on
salvation forces the Church to either “torment” or convert nonbelievers. Presenting
itself as the sole executor of God’s will, this singular spiritual authority acts out of
wrath and intolerance, rather than truly divine motives of forgiveness and love.
Politically, the consequences of one creed claiming jurisdiction over an entire
species’ eternal fate is devastating. If humankind’s greatest prize is controlled by a
single dogmatic authority, then no citizen is free; even “the Sovereign is no longer
Sovereign… over temporal matters.”
794
Although Rousseau’s
exposé
builds a strong case for religious tolerance,
closer scrutiny reveals a serious discrepancy in his argument: Jean-Jacques is wholly
791
The Social Contract
. CW IV.223; OC III.468.
792
The Social Contract
. CW IV.224; OC III.468.
793
The Social Contract
. CW IV.223; OC III.469.
794
As Rousseau had argued in the introduction to
On Civil Religion
, under these circumstances
“Priests are the true masters; Kings are merely their officers.”
The Social Contract
. CW IV.223; OC
III.469.
233
intolerant towards the intolerant. “Without being able to obligate anyone to believe
[its dogmas],” he writes, “the sovereign can banish from the State anyone who does
not believe them.”
795
Expulsion is a legitimate punishment not for the “impious” but
for the “unsociable; for [a citizen] incapable of sincerely loving the laws, justice, and
of giving his life, if need be, for his duty.”
796
Those who reject Civil Religion reject
the very terms of sociability critical to society’s well-being. Such dissenters cannot
be trusted to uphold the rigorous demands of citizenship, or devote sacrificial love to
a value (common welfare) or entity (the state) that transcends their own particular
interests. Failure to accept a civil faith therefore indicates a fundamentally antisocial
pathology punishable by the revocation of citizenship. Rousseau’s unbending tone is
only reinforced by a sudden threat: “If someone who has publicly acknowledged
these same dogmas behaves as though he does not believe them, he should be
punished with death. He has committed the greatest of crimes: he lied before the
law.”
797
These sentiments are discomforting for several reasons. First, Rousseau
advocates banishment without so much as suggesting the possibility of individual
reform or allowing space for public dialogue. Second, he is notably quick to
violence, threatening the death penalty to those who lie “before the law.” And third,
he seems to foster a culture of persecution; Civil Religion’s positive dogmas
presumably exclude atheists from a state in which all citizens must recognize the
795
The Social Contract
. CW IV.222-223; OC III.468.
796
The Social Contract
. CW IV.223; OC III.468.
797
The Social Contract
. CW IV.223; OC III.468.
234
existence of a beneficent Divinity.
798
Rosenblatt argues that “Rousseau’s chapter on
civil religion should be seen as an attack on the political uses of religion by an
absolutizing and oligarchical regime,” yet his Civil Religion seems unapologetically
draconian when taken on its own “simple” terms.
799
How does a model built around
the sanctity of tolerance, fraternity, and individual liberty so swiftly descend into a
platform of forced exile and corporal punishment? Can a truly democratic society
exclude any of its members, particularly atheists? Are such proposals even in accord
with Rousseau’s own Golden Rule, to do “
what is good for you with the least possible
harm to others
”?
800
Or was Lester Crocker correct in labeling this work a
premonition of twentieth century totalitarianism?
Lest the more sensitive readers amongst us conclude that our mercurial author
has finally gone mad, we might offer two explanations in Rousseau’s defense. The
first comes courtesy of Christopher Kelly and Roger Masters who locate within
Civil
Religion
a “‘toughness’… that is often overlooked” in Rousseau’s thought.
801
Certainly, beneath the surface of his gentle reveries on nature, God, and the
possibility of human redemption lies an unyielding backbone aligned with Spartan
severity. Yet even Kelly and Masters soften this disposition, stressing “that for
Rousseau, only behavior—and never an opinion or belief—can be punished by
798
Locke claimed that “those are not at all to be trusted who deny the being of God.” This was
because contracts “[p]romises, covenants, and oaths, which are the bonds of human society, can have
no hold upon an atheist.” Although atheism qualifies as a “private belief” (and thus an individual
liberty),
On Civil Religion
seemed to side with Locke. Each citizen had to uphold its four positive
dogmas, including the recognition of God’s existence. However, as we shall see below, Rousseau’s
position is more ambiguous; he also decried the persecution of atheism in an author’s note from
Julie
.
See: Locke,
A Letter Concerning Toleration
, p. 64.
799
Rosenblatt, p. 267.
800
Second Discourse
. CW III.37-38; OC III.156.
801
CW IV.266, n. 140.
235
society.”
802
Their argument relies upon a generous assessment of Civil Religion’s
jurisdictional limits. Rousseau certainly protects individual faith from magisterial
authority, but he qualifies this liberty by insisting upon compliance with the four
positive dogmas, and buttressing this condition with the threat of physical force. If,
for example, denying the existence of the afterlife constitutes a rejection of the civil
code (and, therefore, a crime against the social order), beliefs would appear to be
punishable by law.
803
No matter the degree, Civil Religion certainly exhibits “toughness.” But this
should hardly assuage our fears. Instead, let us consider Rousseau’s controversial
proposals within the context of his
Social Contract
’s broader aim: legitimizing the
“chains” of denatured society by instituting associations under which equality,
individual liberty and civil unity might flourish. For Rousseau, ecclesiastical dogma
was anathema
804
to such legitimate political reform. Because sectarian creeds posed
ever-present threats to civil and spiritual harmony alike, their influence had to be
contained at all costs. Forced to make difficult choices between a world liberated
from the papist’s grasp and a polity which excluded members destructive of its civic
unity,
On Civil Religion
unequivocally advocates the latter.
805
We might therefore
consider the intolerant terms of Rousseau’s civil faith as a sort of heuristic threat: the
802
CW IV.266, n. 140.
803
Rousseau does not satisfactorily clarify his position, leaving readers to wonder if rejecting the
positive dogmas constitutes a crime against the state, of if citizens might publicly profess adherence
despite private disbelief, the very schism between belief and practice that he attributes Catholic
coercion.
804
According to the
Oxford English Dictionary
, anathema is “anything accursed, or consigned to
damnation,” a sense derived from its Biblical usage as “a thing devoted to evil, an accursed thing” in
Paul’s
Romans
ix.3. I use it here purposefully to suggest the religious terms with which Rousseau’s
phrased the problem of civic unity.
805
Again, we must also bear in mind Rousseau’s depiction of philosophic atheism as its own form of
debilitating fanaticism in
Emile
. See: E 312.
236
lengths to which the author is willing to go in order to ensure that religious practice
does not subvert the requisites of legitimate self-rule.
806
Rousseau’s hard-line stance should come as no surprise. After all, sometimes
man must be
forced
into freedom.
807
This was particularly true in politico-theological
matters where only the combined forces of law, individual consent and group
consensus could counteract sectarianism’s strongly antidemocratic impulses.
Although
Civil Religion
made painfully clear the difficulty of this challenge, grim
reality (as in the
Second Discourse
) did not deter Rousseau from envisioning its
fruition.
808
Quite the opposite. Taking religion as it was and religious associations as
they should be, dissatisfaction provided the impetus for radical reform. Yet even if
his ambitions were well-intentioned, the intolerant terms of his proposal are still
unsettling. In suggesting exile and the death penalty, was Rousseau subverting his
own aims, substituting one form of intolerance (religious) for another (civic)? Did
the “end” of civil liberty necessarily beg such questionable means?
806
As Rousseau stipulates, “the fundamental problem which is solved by the social contract” is to
“[f]ind a form of association that defends and protects the person and goods of each associate with all
the common force, and by means of which each one, uniting with all, nevertheless obeys only himself
and remains as free as before.” Because this solution requires each citizen’s willful support, anyone
who rejects the essential articles of a Civil Religion refuse the terms of legitimate association.
The
Social Contract
. CW IV.138; OC III.360.
807
As Rousseau (in)famously argued, “in order for the social compact not to be an ineffectual formula,
it tacitly includes the following engagement, which alone can give force to the others: that whoever
refuses to obey the general will shall be constrained to do so by the entire body; which means only that
he will be forced to be free.”
The Social Contract
. CW IV.141; OC III.364.
808
If Rousseau’s idealized visions presented a theodicy of sorts (the best possible world), they also
reflected his acute critical awareness and ability to compromise. Even his most seemingly
impracticable proposals establish heights towards which humankind
should
strive, no matter if
evidence suggests we will fall short; this is what I have termed Rousseau’s “heuristic idealism”
throughout. To my mind, the best illustration of this dynamic is revealed in a comparison between
The
Social Contract
and
On the Government of Poland
. In his
Contract
, Rousseau lists apparently
necessary qualities of people “suited for legislation” which, by the authors own admission, are “hard to
find together.” (In all of Europe only Corsica was “still… capable of legislation.”) Poland—a large,
diffuse, disunited nation threatened by foreign invaders on multiple fronts—was particularly ill-suited
to the
Contract
’s terms. Yet this did not prevent Rousseau from earnestly envisioning reforms which
would allow the Poles rewrite their history and work towards a more legitimate political future.
The
Social Contract
. CW IV.162; OC III.390-391.
237
As an attempt to marry religious and political faiths under a liberal democratic
framework,
On Civil Religion
marked an auspicious beginning. Even Rousseau
himself seemed unsatisfied with its outcome. Subsequent correspondences to his
friend Moultou and the pastor Usteri find him both clarifying and even modifying his
position.
809
He further refined his stance in the
Letter to Beaumont
, adhering to
Civil
Religion
’s core assertions while abandoning its more reactionary threats. Rousseau
began by repeating a refrain consistent throughout his works: “if man is made for
society, the truest Religion is also the most social and the most humane.”
810
Still, he
forthrightly admitted that “this sentiment is subject to great difficulties from the
historical account and the facts that contradict it.”
811
As he elaborated,
I neither say nor think there is no good Religion on earth. But I do
say, and it is only too true, that there is none among those that are or
have been dominant that has not cruelly wounded humanity. All
parties have tormented their brothers, all have offered to God
sacrifices of human blood. Whatever the source of these
contradictions, they exist. Is it a crime to want to eliminate them?
812
Here, in a nutshell, was Rousseau’s self-defense of
Civil Religion
. His text did not
categorically condemn “Religion on earth”; it merely recognized a problem in need of
redress, the fact that “dominant” religions had scorched God’s earth, shed man’s
blood, and wounded social unity.
As explanations go, Rousseau’s was conspicuously unrepentant. He forced a
dubious distinction between practical observation and profane censure, one further
blurred by his subsequent critique of the meek masses. If creeds had “cruelly
809
See: CC XVI.2626, 2662, 2768; and XV.2825.
810
Rousseau completes this sentence with a refutation of ontological guilt: “For God wants us to be as
he made us, and if it were true that he had made us wicked, it would be disobeying him to want to
cease being so.”
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.54; OC IV.969. Readers should compare this with
Emile
. E 212, 281.
811
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.54; OC IV.970.
812
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.55; OC IV.970-971.
238
wounded humanity,” their followers voiced little objection. As Rousseau lamented,
“[p]eople submit in silence,” conforming without protest to the pernicious precepts of
domineering papists.
813
Despite appearances, Jean-Jacques was not simply decrying
the subservience of a slavish flock. He viewed such complicity as a natural reaction
to clerical coercion. Indeed, his point was even firmer: outer compliance did not
reveal inward complicity because individual belief systems could not be bullied into
submission.
He was hardly the first to air such opinions. Luther had argued forcefully that
outward obedience offered little proof of sincere conviction; unlike motives or faith,
good works were easily contrived.
814
And in his
Letter Concerning Toleration
, Locke
insisted that “no man can, [even] if he would, conform his faith to the dictates of
another.”
815
Because “the life and power of true religion consists in the inward and
full persuasion of the true mind[,] faith is not faith without believing.”
816
Furthermore, for Locke “the liberty of conscience is every man’s natural right.”
817
Rousseau likewise championed the sanctity of individual conscience, and agreed that
813
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.57; OC IV.973.
814
We must recall that Luther, unlike Rousseau, was (as Quentin Skinner perfectly puts it) “obsessed
by the idea of man’s complete unworthiness.” His argument that “[g]ood works do not make a good
man, but a good man does good works” refuted the papal authority in granting “indulgences”
(remissions of temporal sins through penance), but it also served to instill a self-deprecating fear of
God in a species profoundly incapable of affecting its eternal fate. Luther,
The Freedom of a Christian
in
Selections From His Writings
, p. 69. Quentin Skinner,
The Foundations of Modern Political
Thought: Volume Two: The Age of Reformation
(London and New York: Cambridge University Press,
1978), p. 3.
815
Locke,
A Letter Concerning Toleration
, p. 19.
816
Ibid., p. 19.
817
Ibid., p. 65
239
external force did not cultivate internal conviction. Superficial compliance to
orthodox precepts was just that: “only in appearance.”
818
The “inconsistency… noted between [subjects’] morality and their actions”
was therefore less the fault of individuals than institutions which demanded public
affirmation of opinions private by nature.
819
As Rousseau countered in
Civil
Religion
, only the most general tenets shared by all could serve as a basis for civil
communion; individual beliefs lay beyond the jurisdiction of Church and State alike.
Reiterating this argument in his
Letter to Beaumont
, Rousseau wondered:
Why does one man have the right of inspection over another man’s
belief, and why does the State have it over the belief of the Citizens?
It is because it is assumed that what men believe determines their
morality, and that their conduct in this life is dependent upon their
ideas about the life to come. If this is not true, what difference does it
make what they believe or what they pretend to believe?
820
The answer is none, so long as citizens uphold the common duties necessary to
preserve their polity’s well-being.
821
In society, “everyone has the right to find out
whether another person believes himself obligated to be just, and the Sovereign has
the right to examine the reasons on which each person bases this obligation.”
822
This
standard did not, however, apply to an individual’s faith. As Rousseau emphasized,
for “opinions that are not connected to morality, that do not influence actions in any
818
For a discussion of the problem between appearance and reality used as a justification for
Rousseau’s sense of individual innocence, see Chapter 3 above.
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.57; OC
IV.973.
819
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.57; OC IV.973.
820
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.57; OC IV.973.
821
Locke similarly argued that a heathen who rejected “both Testaments” should not be “punished as a
pernicious citizen,” because such beliefs affect neither the security of magisterial power nor “the
estates of the people.” Even though he “readily grant[s] that these opinions are false and absurd,”
Locke maintained that “the business of laws is not to provide for the truth of opinions, but for the
safety and security of the commonwealth, and of every particular man’s goods and person.” Locke,
A
Letter Concerning Toleration
, pp. 55-56.
822
Letter to Beaumont
. Beaumont CW IX.57; OC IV.973.
240
way, and that do not transgress Laws, each person has only his own judgment as a
master on these, and no one has either right or interest in prescribing his way of
thinking for others.”
823
Jean-Jacques further developed this distinction between public and private
faith in his
Letters Written from the Mountain
. Beginning with a tripartite division of
religion into dogma, morality, and worship (“which is only ceremonial”), he split
“dogma further into two parts, namely the one which in setting forth the principles of
our duties serves as a foundation for morality, and the one which, purely of faith,
contains only speculative dogmas.”
824
Rousseau’s civil faith was concerned only
with the former, foundational codes which define society’s moral will.
As for the part of Religion that deals with morality, that is to say
justice, the public good, obedience to the natural and positive Laws,
the social virtues and all the duties of man and Citizen, it is the
business of government to take cognizance of them. It is on this point
alone that Religion falls directly under its jurisdiction, and that it must
banish not error, of which it is not the judge, but every harmful
sentiment that tends to cut the social knot.
825
As his stance on Christianity made clear, religion takes different forms, each with its
own unique function. Those that serve morality, justice, the public good and civic
duty define the terms of social relations, and therefore fall under the domain of
sovereign jurisdiction.
Reiterating his claim that “it is important for the State not to be without
Religion… for serious reasons, upon which I have strongly insisted throughout,”
Rousseau nonetheless argued that it would be better to do without “than to have a
barbarous and persecuting [creed] that, tyrannizing the Laws themselves, would
823
Letter to Beaumont
. Beaumont CW IX.57; OC IV.973.
824
Letters Written From the Mountain
(First Letter). CW IX.139; OC III.694.
825
Letters Written From the Mountain
(First Letter). CW IX.140; OC III.694-695.
241
thwart the duties of the Citizen.”
826
In this worst of possible scenarios, a wise
Legislator is left with only two options:
the first is to establish a purely civil Religion, which includes all
fundamental dogmas of every good Religion, all dogmas truly useful
to either a universal or a particular society… The other expedient is to
leave Christianity as it is in its genuine spirit: free, disengaged from all
bonds of flesh, with no other obligation than that of conscience, no
other constraint in its dogmas than morals and Laws.
827
Because “the Gospel has only one aim… to call and save all men,” and because this
lesson is fundamentally removed from worldly concerns (as Jesus himself said “a
thousand times”), “Christianity as it is” could not combat the tyranny of a “barbarous
and persecuting” creed. Under such circumstances, Legislators had only one feasible
strategy: “removing the Christian Religion from national Institutions” and instituting
a Civil Religion. In so urging Rousseau claimed to “establish what is best for the
human race,” a religious association distinct from (and protective of) interior faith
which actively fostered civic duty.
His solution to the politico-theological problem therefore demanded sharp
jurisdictional boundaries, a clear understanding of the varieties of religious practice,
and a sober assessment of religion’s strengths and weaknesses when “considered in
relation to society.” The only way to preserve Christianity was to keep it out of
politics. This argument was consistent with the lesson (as Rousseau understood it) of
Jesus, the first to completely divest religion of corporeal concerns. Furthermore, as
we have also seen, Rousseau believed that “purely spiritual” faiths tended towards
political apathy or (when appropriated by theocrats and papists) dogmatic intolerance,
and were thus ill-suited to the specific demands of citizenship. By contrast, the only
826
Letters Written From the Mountain
(First Letter). CW IX.148; OC III.705.
827
Letters Written From the Mountain
(First Letter). CW IX.148; OC III.705-706.
242
way to protect society
and
preserve true adherence to divine order was to implement a
“purely civil” faith. If Civil Religion discouraged dogmatism, cultivated civic unity,
and conformed to the general will, it also upheld the sanctity of personal religious
belief so necessary to keep man attuned to his divinely-scribed nature.
Rousseau’s dual commitment to religious piety and individual liberty are easy
to overlook in a text which errs on the side of authoritarianism. After all, he presents
exile and corporal punishment as threats necessary to protect a greater good. Yet for
Rousseau, attacks upon individual faith had
always
aroused such unbending hostility.
Consider these two examples of righteous indignation from earlier works, first in his
August 30, 1756
Letter to Voltaire
and then in
Julie
:
I am indignant that the faith of everyone is not in the most perfect
liberty, and that man dares control the interior of consciences, where
he is unable to penetrate, as if it depended on us to believe in matters
where demonstration has no place.
828
[N]o true believer can possibly practice intolerance or persecution. If I
were a judge, and the law prescribed the death penalty against atheists,
I would begin by having burned for atheism anyone who came to turn
in someone else.
829
To Voltaire, Rousseau forthrightly denounced those who would dare “control the
interior of consciences.” And in
Julie
, he suggested that those who condemned non-
believers to death were themselves more deserved of execution.
828
Letter from Rousseau to Voltaire
, August 18, 1756. CW III.119; OC IV.1072.
829
The context of these lines is particularly revealing. A letter detailing Wolmar’s atheism notes that
“he had in his whole life found no more than three Priests who believed in God.” In an author’s note,
Rousseau qualifies this third-person statement: “God forbid I should approve these harsh and
outrageous assertions; I merely affirm that there are people who make them and whose excess is only
too often justified by the clergy of all countries and all sects.” Although, as we have seen, Rousseau
himself charged ecclesiasts with irreligiosity, here he claims to want only to provide “clarity [in] my
sentiment on this point”: namely, that genuine religious belief and intolerance are mutually
incompatible.
Julie
. CW VI.482n; OC II.589n.
243
If Rousseau sustained these severe sentiments throughout his career,
On Civil
Religion
nonetheless marked a turning point, a struggle to apply his convictions to
practice. It was the concrete culmination of a vague idea initially conceived in 1756
as “a sort of profession of faith that the laws can impose.”
830
Even at this nascent
stage, however, Rousseau sounded obdurate. He approached the task of religious
reform as though it were war, warning that “there can exist Religions which attack the
foundation of society, and… it is necessary to begin by exterminating these Religions
in order to assure the peace of the State.”
831
So were set the harsh tones of a battle he
returned to wage in full more than six years later.
Why did Rousseau strike so violent a pose from beginning to end? In a 1755
letter to Voltaire, he made plain that sometimes “evil is such that the very causes that
gave birth to it are necessary to prevent it from becoming larger. It is the sword that
must be left in the wound for fear that the wounded person will die when it is
removed.”
832
Sometimes, evil cannot be completely eradicated; and sometimes, as
the
Second Discourse
and
Social Contract
argued, the very faculties which corrupt us
can facilitate our salvation; sometimes, in these extreme instances, you have to fight
fire with fire.
Desperate times may require desperate measures, but never apathy or
resignation. This was precisely the challenge posed in
Civil Religion
. In claiming to
solely represent God, clerics undermined His benevolence and misrepresented His
830
Letter from Rousseau to Voltaire
, August 18, 1756. CW III.119; OC IV.1073.
831
As in
Civil Religion
, Rousseau claimed that “intolerance [was] easily the most odious” of dogmas
meriting proscription. This was because an intolerant person “imagines that one cannot be a good man
without believing everything that he believes, and damns unmercifully all those who do not think like
him.” This was the very critique he presented in
The Social Contract
, and a crime attributed to papists
throughout his writings (specifically when denouncing Original Sin).
Letter from Rousseau to
Voltaire
, August 18, 1756. CW III.119; OC IV.1073.
832
Letter from Rousseau to Voltaire
, September 10, 1755. CW III.106; OC III.226-227.
244
very will. Their coercive creeds crippled social unity, assailed individual liberty, and
perverted His magnificent order. Rather than remain complacent, Rousseau urged
readers to fight back. After all, the secular and spiritual damage wrought by papists
could
only
be repaired through radical reform. Only by instituting a faith which
rejected despotic dogma and expunged religious intolerance could Jean-Jacques’
vision of secular and spiritual salvation achieve fruition.
833
Towards this end, Rousseau made one essential demand. He asked that we
keep our relationship with God to ourselves, and allow others the same freedom.
Consider as evidence his response to being pressed on a theological point of
contention:
after telling [an interlocutor] I do not understand it and do not care
about understanding it, I would ask him as decently as I could to mind
his own business, and it he persisted, I would leave him there.
That is the only principle on which something stable and equitable can
be established about disputes of Religion. Lacking that, everyone
establishes on his own part what is in question, there will never be
agreement on anything, people will never in their lives understand one
another, and Religion, which ought to make men happy, will always
cause their greatest ills.
834
In short,
mind your own business
. This was less a suggestion than an imperative.
Religion “ought to make men happy” because it affirmed our connection to God and
His benevolent order. Doctrinal differences subverted this relationship, serving only
to enflame corporeal divisions. Since men could never settle such “disputes,” they
must agree to not agree. This was wholly possible because, as Rousseau argued,
833
If Civil Religion’s more reactionary proposals reflect this adamant condition, Rousseau’s model
also drew upon the dictate of his Golden Rule, to do “
what is good
…
with the least possible harm to
others
.”
Second Discourse
. CW III.37-38; OC III.156.
834
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.57; OC IV.973.
245
every believer regardless of creed shared certain fundamental tenets.
835
And only
these most general of beliefs could foster an inclusive, unifying, truly
civil
morality
grounded in religious piety.
Perhaps
On Civil Religion
failed to strike the right balance. Perhaps it
succumbed too heavily to its author’s fear of dogmatism and preoccupation with
social order. Or perhaps it was subverted by conflicting loyalties, by the “strange
confusion of the profane and the sacred” Robert Derathé identified in its manifold
claims.
836
Rousseau accepted man’s needs as creations of God dependent upon
divine guidance, and denatured creatures dependent upon legitimate institutions. He
examined religion as a source of moral virtue, and religious associations as a catalyst
for human oppression. He identified the necessity of social harmony and the threats
to this order. And he concluded that the only way to truly serve mankind—to satisfy
our equally compelling spiritual and secular needs—was to draw from religion only
those principles we knew were true (no matter our creed), while forging the
legitimized chains necessary to preserve our freedom. As with the treatise on
Poland
,
Civil Religion
sincerely struggled to implement a social contract under less-than-ideal
circumstances.
In the final analysis, Rousseau refused to abandon his commitment to either
spiritual or corporeal improvement because he believed they were so deeply
interrelated. Society needed social order, just as individuals needed faith. After all,
835
In this, Rousseau’s stance mirrors the Vicar’s deistic anti-sectarianism. This shared beliefs also
serve as Civil Religion’s four “positive” dogmas.
836
Derathé interpreted this “confusion” as evidence of escapism, arguing that Rousseau had vainly
attempted to tidy up the paradoxes and dualisms so characteristic of his works. Judith Shklar had
levied a similar charge against Rousseau in
Men and Citizens
. OC III.1505. For a rebuttal to Shklar’s
argument, see Chapter Two above.
246
human beings were
both
creations of God and denatured individuals. We were
blessed with conscience
and
free will, natural goodness
and
the ability to err. God
gave us perfectibility, the faculty that enabled our history of decline
and
allowed us
the means of self-redemption. Civil Religion reflects this tense dialectic: it is both
pious and profane, pessimistic and idealistic, civil and intolerant, civic-minded and
individualistic, reasoned and emotive, historically-grounded and forward-thinking. In
striking so many dissonant chords it grabs our attention, prodding us to accept
religion and man
as they are
, and envision the relationship between religion and
politics
as it should be
.
247
Chapter 6: The Road to Vincennes
I do not mean… that one can be virtuous without Religion; I held this erroneous
opinion for a long time, but now I am only too disabused.
—Rousseau,
Letter to d’Alembert
837
I have suffered too much in this life not to expect another one. All the subtleties of
Metaphysics will not make me doubt for a moment the immortality of the soul, and a
beneficent Providence. I feel it, I believe it, I wish it, I hope it, I shall defend it until
my last breath; and it will be, of all the controversies that I shall have sustained, the
only one where my interest will not be forgotten.
—Rousseau,
Letter to Voltaire
838
Taking organized religion as it was, Rousseau imagined a civil faith as it
should be: serving both God and man, facilitating moral virtue and political
prosperity, and occluding the violent intolerance characteristic of dogmatic
sectarianism. His prescription was in part reactionary, a positive alternative to the
divisive creed of Roman Catholicism. Instilling fear of a rancorous God amongst
subjects, the “religion of the priests” partitioned humankind into two mutually
antagonistic camps: those who either conformed to or rejected Catholic tenets. The
837
Although Rousseau insists that one cannot “be virtuous without religion,” he adds a significant
qualifier: “a Believer can sometimes, from motives of purely social virtue, abstain from certain actions,
indifferent in themselves and which do not immediately involve the conscience, such as going to the
theater in a place where it is not good to tolerate it.” Notably, a secular sense of “social virtue” can
serve a religious moral function. Without debasing the moral necessity of religion, he defers to a
pragmatic position: in his example, both the religious and socially virtuous individual would shun a
Genevan theater. The end result (abstinence) is more significant than the source of guidance. This
position is wholly consistent with Rousseau’s broader vision of political reform, one which employs
social or artificial remedies to cultivate virtue in a denatured society. In addition, this argument
suggests a mutually beneficial relationship between spiritual and secular morality, one in which a
social remedy mimics the benefits of religious piety.
Letter to d’Alembert
. CW X.322n; OC V.89n.
Readers should also compare this to Rousseau’s claim, ten years later, that “[t]o root out all belief in
God from the heart of man is to destroy all virtue there.”
Letter to Franquières
. CW VIII.266-167;
OC IV.1142.
838
Letter to Voltaire
, August 18, 1756. CW III.121; OC IV.1075.
248
former were deemed eligible for divine redemption, while the latter were condemned
as heathens and sentenced to an eternity of damnation.
839
As Rousseau noted, this brash verdict followed an equally egregious
assumption. Papal authorities believed themselves to be the sole mediators and
arbiters of a divine will that was, in fact, ultimately incomprehensible to the human
mind. And in claiming to exclusively represent the Author of all things, clerics
actually disserved their presumed Creator and His creations alike. Perpetuating
dogmatic myths of a sinful species and punitive deity, they cast a dark shadow over
the true beauty, wisdom and order characteristic of our divinely-scribed world.
Furthermore, in damning human ontology as fatally flawed, Roman Catholicism
decreed that remission (and, hence, redemption) was possible only through strict
adherence to its tenets. Rousseau sharply disagreed, dismissing orthodox positions on
Original Sin, miracles, and revelation, while soundly rejecting the Church’s assertion
that it alone possessed the authority to mete out man’s salvation.
Virulent anti-clericalism notwithstanding, Jean-Jacques was hardly irreligious.
Rather, he argued that religion and faith were keystones of a virtuous polity. The
problem was simply that Catholicism
840
did not cultivate the values (tolerance,
liberty, and equality under the law) essential to a vibrant democratic culture’s welfare.
In remedy, Rousseau offered a bold alternative: a Civil Religion that both enriched
corporeal life and upheld divine order.
839
Readers should also note the socially divisive consequences of this verdict. As Maurice Cranston
describes, Rousseau’s was “an age when nonconformity was everywhere severely penalized.” This
phenomenon was particularly acute in sectarian matters, as the infamous Calas affair and routine
persecution of non-Catholics illustrates. Cranston,
The Noble Savage
, p. 1.
840
As we saw in Chapter 5, Catholicism epitomized the social and political failings that (in
On Civil
Religion
) he attributed to all dogmatic and theocratic creeds.
249
The ambitiousness of his solution cannot be understated. Rousseau did not
merely dismiss the merits of papism; he attempted to found a new religion entirely, a
“purely civil” faith that served God and man alike. Civil Religion certainly adhered
to foundational Christian beliefs (in an omnipotent Creator, the existence of an
afterlife, and a divine moral code) and drew upon a Protestant model of individual
worship.
841
Yet it was also deeply secular, designed in conformity with the requisites
of a legitimate polity established in
The Social Contract
. Where Catholicism molded
subjects who cowered before God and monarch alike, Rousseau claimed that his civic
creed cultivated autonomous, pious citizens. Where clerics damned mankind as
Adam’s infected progeny, the Genevan dared to suggest that, as naturally innocent
creations, salvation was possible in this world
and
the next.
From whence did he summon the nerve to voice such radical beliefs? We
might here recall that Rousseau once described Jesus and Socrates as his spiritual and
moral forebears.
842
Like these storied figures, he acted as a man possessed by a
higher calling. Jean-Jacques may have lacked the self-possession of Socrates and the
sheer fearlessness of Jesus. But, as his motto reminds us, he shared their commitment
to reveal the truth no matter the cost. Following divinely-instilled missions, Jesus and
Socrates
843
sacrificed individual welfare to point their slumbering peers towards
841
According to Rousseau, “the two fundamental points of the Reform… [were] to acknowledge the
Bible as rule of one’s belief, and not to admit any other interpreter of the meaning of the Bible than
oneself.” This was because Reformers had established “the individual mind… as the sole interpreter of
Scripture” while rejecting “the authority of the Church.”
Letters Written From the Mountain: Second
Letter
. CW IX.154; OC III.712-713.
842
See:
Letter to Beaumont
(Fragment 5). CW IX.89; OC IV.1016.
843
As Socrates asserted, “I want you to think of my adventures as a sort of pilgrimage undertaken to
establish the truth of the oracle.” The reference is to the Delphic oracle, to whose divine injunction
Socrates attributed his calling as a gadfly. See:
The Apology
, 20D-22A in Plato,
The Last Days of
Socrates
, pp. 49-51. What Socrates considered divine inspiration (the priestess’ pronouncements),
250
redemption amidst a world beset by decay. Rousseau was similarly consumed,
drawing upon faith in divine beneficence and human potential to dream of—and
struggle to realize—a better future for all.
The Genevan attributed his intense convictions to a life-changing event. Like
Paul on the road to Damascus, he was struck by a supernatural epiphany that occurred
en route
to Vincennes.
844
Rousseau described his conversion as the epicenter of his
career, the catalyst to his every
oeuvre
. A moment of profound clarity and physical
exhaustion, transcendent bliss and tearful collapse, Rousseau’s transformation was
also, quite notably, Christian in form and Pagan in content. Seemingly touched by
the hand of God, he was reborn as a proselyte
845
for human glory and corporeal
redemption: his spiritual awakening crystallized as a mandate of secular reform. A
stunning amalgam of the themes with which we have grappled throughout, the road
on which Jean-Jacques began life anew marks a particularly fitting point for our own
study to conclude.
* * * * *
modern science suggests were in fact ethylene-induced hallucinations. See: William J. Broad, “For
Delphic Oracle, Fumes and Visions,”
The New York Times
, March 19, 2002.
844
Rousseau was visiting Diderot, who had been imprisoned in the dungeons of Vincennes on July 24,
1749 for anti-Catholic writings, and had recently been moved to a
château
where he was permitted to
receive visitors. For a summary of the political climate that led to Diderot’s arrest—specifically, of the
rise in censorship following the Austrian Succession—see: Cranston,
Jean-Jacques: The Early Life
and Work of Jean-Jacques Rousseau
, 1712-1754. (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1982),
pp. 226-227.
845
In
The Confessions
, Rousseau reveals that his uncle was a preacher, and that he had considered a
career as a minister (which he forewent due to financial considerations): “I preferred to be a minister
[to a watchmaker or a lawyer], for I found it very fine to preach. But the small income from my
mother’s property which was to be divided between my brother and myself was not enough for
furthering my studies.” CW V.21; OC I.25.
251
Rousseau changed creeds twice in his life, from Protestantism to Catholicism
and back to Protestantism. If the first
846
was juvenile, a trite decision he made as a
teenage runaway charmed by a Savoyard priest over dinner and fine Frangi wine, the
second
847
was commonly viewed as a matter of expediency “to recover his rights and
privileges as a citizen of Geneva.”
848
No matter the circumstances, neither of these
formal conversions suggest a calling in the Biblical sense of the term.
849
Fittingly
enough for our paradoxical author, Rousseau’s most Christian conversion—in form if
not content—was to political philosophy.
Jean-Jacques’ first and most elaborate description of this life-changing event
appeared in a series of 1762
850
correspondences to the censor Malesherbes.
851
He
846
In his sixteenth year, Rousseau missed his city’s curfew, and found himself locked out of Geneva’s
gates. In reaction, he fled, making his way to Savoy. He there met Benoit de Pontverre, the first of
two figures he credits as inspiration for his fictional Savoyard Vicar. Pontverre took the wayward lad
into his home, and urged him to renounce his native Protestantism for Catholicism. As Rousseau
writes, “I did not dream of changing religion; and very far from growing accustomed so quickly to that
idea, I envisaged it only with a horror that ought to have kept it away from me for a long time; I only
wanted not to anger these people who were cajoling me with that intention; I wanted to cultivate their
benevolence and to leave them the hope of success by appearing less well armed than I was in fact.”
Passivity and purported politeness aside, he did in fact convert, and soon departed to Annency where
he met the woman entrusted with his care—Louise Eleonor de Warens.
The Confessions
. CW V.39;
OC I.46-47.
847
As Rousseau wrote after his Protestant conversion of 1754, “I am attached in good faith to that true
and holy Religion, and I shall be until my last breath. I wish always to be united to that church in
public as I am in the depths of my heart, and however consoling it will be for me personally to
participate in the communion of believers, I desire it, I assure you, more for the edification of those
believers and for the honour of the Church than for my own advantage, for it would not be right for
people to think that a man of good faith who reasons cannot be a member of Jesus Christ.” From: CC
XII.2108, as translated in Cranston,
The Solitary Self
, p. 32. For the displeasure this declaration
elicited amongst the Parisian
philosophes
(particularly d’Alembert), see p. 33.
848
Despite this cynical view held even amongst his friends, Rousseau insisted that his Protestant faith
was sincere and passionate. In support, Cranston argues that Jean-Jacques’ conversion back to
Protestantism was not simply guided by practical or strategic concerns, and in fact was wholly
consistent with Jean-Jacques’ increasing commitment to “lead a thoroughly virtuous life.” As
Cranston continues, “Rousseau saw himself as having become a true believer in the Reformed religion,
at least as he understood it.” Cranston,
The Noble Savage
, p. 1.
849
The
Oxford English Dictionary
defines a Biblical calling as either a “summons, invitation, or
impulse of God to salvation or to his service,” or “the inward feeling or conviction of a divine call.”
850
Rousseau wrote four letters in this series to Malesherbes, dating from January 4 to January 28,
1762. See: CW V.572-583; OC I.1130-1147.
851
As John M. S. Allison describes, Malesherbe’s relationship to Rousseau was “friendly but always
frank.” Their interactions nonetheless were strained following the publication of
Emile
and
The Social
252
began these
Letters
much as he would his later
Confessions
: with a bold claim that
they contained “the true picture of my character and the true motives for all my
behavior.”
852
The “true picture” depicted Rousseau as a defeated, disillusioned
wanderer who possessed a “natural love of solitude which has done nothing but
increase in proportion as I have gotten to know men better.”
853
He attributed this
propensity to both temperament and circumstance: men had caused him to “take
fright” and withdraw, while his nature predisposed him to passivity. “The active life
has nothing that tempts me,” he asserted. “I would a hundred times rather consent to
never doing anything than to doing something in spite of myself; and I have thought a
hundred times that I would not have lived too unhappily at the Bastille, since I would
not be restricted to anything at all except to staying there.”
854
This manifesto of inactivity was nonetheless incomplete, for Rousseau also
admitted to harboring ambition as a youth.
855
He attributed his taste for achievement
to the Pagan writings of Plutarch, heroic tales which he encountered at age six and
memorized by age eight.
856
These epic stories moved his heart and (much as the
Contract
. In a letter to Rousseau dated November 13, 1762, Malesherbes praised “that spirit of truth
so strong, courageous, and passionately virtuous which pervades all your writing,” but regretted that he
“found myself at odds… in regard to the most important principles which you have discussed in your
more recent works.” See: Allison,
Lamoignon de Malesherbes: Defender and Reformer of the French
Monarchy, 1721-1794
, (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1938), p. 32.
852
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.572; OC I.1130.
853
According to Rousseau, the cause of his reclusiveness “is nothing other than that indomitable spirit
of freedom which… comes to me less from pride than from laziness; but this laziness is unbelievable;
everything makes it take fright; the slightest duties of civil life are unbearable to it.”
Letters to
Malesherbes
. CW V.572-573; OC I.1131-1132.
854
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.573; OC I.1132.
855
“Nevertheless,” Rousseau confides, “in my youth I made several efforts to succeed.”
Letters to
Malesherbes
. CW V.573; OC I.1132-1133.
856
From these readings, Rousseau writes, “was formed in my heart that heroic and romantic taste
which has done nothing but increase up to the present, and which ended by disgusting me with
everything.”
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.574; OC I.1134.
253
Bible had affected Augustine)
857
caused him to “shed buckets of tears.”
858
They also
caused him significant grief, planting dreams of glory that were soon “soured by the
injustices I had suffered, and by those I had been the witness of.”
859
At the time of his writing, only two things assuaged Rousseau’s regret:
daydreams and faith. Dismayed with the “society of men,” he retreated (as in the
Reveries
) into his “imagination which charmed me all the more since I could cultivate
it without effort, without risk, and always find it reliable and as I needed it to be.”
860
And (as in
The Confessions
) he insisted that the Lord would ultimately affirm his
goodness: “I do not fear at all being seen as I am. I know my great flaws, and I feel
all my vices keenly. With all that I will die full of hope in the Supreme God, and
very persuaded that of all the men I have known in my life, none was better than I.”
861
These therapeutic asides notwithstanding, Rousseau struggled mightily.
“Forty years of my life [passed] this way,” he bemoaned.
862
“[D]issatisfied with
myself and with others, I fruitlessly sought to break the bonds that were keeping me
attached to that society which I esteemed so little, and which chained me to
occupations that were least to my taste through needs that I considered to be those of
nature and which were only those of opinion.”
863
In short, he would have been far
happier left to his own devices and free to pursue an unfettered existence. The bonds
that “attached” him to society—social relations generally, and employment
857
See: Augustine,
Confessions
, VIII.xii.29, pp. 152-153.
858
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.574; OC I.1134.
859
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.575; OC I.1134.
860
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.575; OC I.1135.
861
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.574; OC I.1133. Readers should compare this passage with:
The
Confessions
. CW V.5; OC I.5.
862
In fact, only thirty-seven years of Rousseau’s life had passed. His epiphany on the road to
Vincennes occurred in October of 1749. His first visit to Diderot was in August of the same year.
Trousson and Eigeldinger,
Rousseau au jour le jour
, p. 53.
863
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.575; OC I.1135.
254
specifically—nonetheless proved difficult to break. Rousseau was lost in the world,
disgusted with denatured society yet unsure of how to liberate himself, when a stroke
of fate delivered him from his monotonous stalemate: “Suddenly a fortunate chance
happened to enlighten me about what I had to do for myself, and to think about my
fellows about whom my heart was ceaselessly in contradiction with my mind, and
whom I still felt myself brought to love along with so many reasons to hate them.”
864
This “singularly epoch-making moment in my life” occurred on the road to
Vincennes.
865
The catalyst to his revelation was a small advertisement in
le Mercure
de France
for the Dijon Academy’s essay contest. Although Rousseau later
responded to the question posed (
has the restoration of the sciences and arts tended
to purify morals
?)
866
with his prize-winning
First Discourse
, it’s reading produced a
far more immediate effect.
If anything has ever resembled a sudden inspiration, it is the motion
that was caused in me by that reading; suddenly I felt my mind dazzled
by a thousand lights; crowds of lively ideas presented themselves at
the same time with a strength and a confusion that threw me into an
inexpressible perturbation; I feel my head seized by a dizziness similar
to drunkenness. A violent palpitation oppresses me, makes me sick to
my stomach; not being able to breath any more while walking, I let
myself fall under one of the trees of the avenue, and I pass a half-hour
there in such an agitation that when I got up again I noticed the whole
front of my coat soaked with my tears without having felt that I shed
them.
867
The
Oxford English Dictionary
defines “inspiration” as the “special immediate action
or influence of the Spirit of God (or of some divinity or supernatural being) upon the
864
The passivity of Rousseau’s language is noteworthy. While he was paralyzed (by a strong
ambivalence towards his “fellows”), chance intruded “to enlighten me about what I had to do for
myself.”
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.575; OC I.1135.
865
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.575; OC I.1135.
866
First Discourse
. CW II.1; OC III.1. The announcement appeared in the October, 1749 edition of
le
Mercure de France
. OC III.1237.
867
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.575; OC I.1134.
255
human mind or soul.”
868
Rousseau’s “sudden inspiration” bore precisely these marks
of divine intervention. His eyes “dazzled by a thousand lights,” his mind crowded by
a host of “lively ideas,” his head “seized” in a dizzying state, a “violent” force
overwhelmed him. Nauseous, overcome, and robbed of breath, he collapsed in a
puddle of his own tears.
Rousseau was certainly not the first to be floored by a supernatural revelation.
As Augustine’s
Confessions
detail, a similarly agonizing state of conflict preceded the
Saint’s conversion to Christianity. His soul became a battlefield “between different
wills” characterized by their “mutual incompatibility.”
869
He was “torn apart in a
painful condition,” bound by the chains of earthly desires and initially unable to make
a whole-hearted leap of faith to Christ.
870
“Twisting and turning in my chain”—
namely, attachment to physical desire—“until it would break completely,” Augustine
confided that “the nearer approached the moment of time when I would become
different [converted] the greater the horror of it struck me.”
871
Paralyzed in a “state
of suspense,” caught between deeply conflicting urges (earthly habit and divine
inspiration), his “painful” transformation finally coalesced in a moment of clarity:
wholly dedicating himself to God, he concluded that life was a trial “to be endured,
not loved.”
872
868
More specifically, the term “inspiration” is used to describe “that divine influence under which the
books of Scripture are held to have been written.”
869
Augustine,
Confessions
, pp. 146 & 150.
870
Ibid., p. 150.
871
Ibid., pp. 150-151.
872
Ibid., p. 202.
256
Likewise, Rousseau’s illumination physically overpowered him, imbued him
with faith, and culminated in revelation.
873
However, these similarities
notwithstanding, one significant distinction separates the two conversions:
Augustine’s followed a protracted, self-conscious struggle to convert
874
whereas
Rousseau was quite literally struck out of the blue. As the
Letters to Malesherbes
make clear, he had dreamt far more of retreat (from society) than (individual) reform.
Only a series of fortuitous coincidences led him to Vincennes with
le Mercure
in
hand, where he read a brief question from Dijon that abruptly, intensely, and without
rational explanation,
875
coalesced all the contradictory thoughts in his brain and sent
him reeling to the ground.
Rousseau provides little evidence that he had sought, much less anticipated,
such a dramatic transformation. Yet unlike his formal conversions to Catholicism
and Protestantism, this moment marked a deep and permanent change. The sense of
duty that he actively eschewed for so long had suddenly become manifest. Touched
by otherworldly inspiration, Rousseau was reborn as a proselyte compelled to convey
that single brief illumination. He had finally found his calling or, more precisely, his
calling had finally found him.
873
In addition, the fortuitous appearance of a text (Athanasius’
The Life of Antony
and
le Mercure de
France
) provided the catalyst for the conversions of both Augustine and Rousseau.
874
As Augustine writes, “I supposed that the reason for my postponing ‘from day to day’ the moment
when I would despise worldly ambition and follow you was that I had not seen any certainty by which
to direct my course.” It was only after encountering the story of Saint Antony’s life that Augustine
recognized “the day had now come when I stood naked to myself, and my conscience complained
against me,” pushing him to wholly embrace God. Ibid., p. 145.
875
This absence of reasoning further distinguishes the conversions of Rousseau and Augustine. The
Saint’s leap of faith to God was predicated upon a sophisticated metaphysical analysis of the dangers
of a divided soul, an affliction whose only possible, rational cure was the whole-hearted embrace of
God. See: Augustine,
Confessions
, pp. 137-141. For Augustine’s comparably reasoned argument on
time, see: 221-245.
257
In this regard, Rousseau’s epiphany more closely resembles Saint Paul’s
storied conversion on the road to Damascus. Paul was a Roman citizen and
Hellenized Jew, “a Hebrew born of Hebrews” in approximately 10 AD.
876
In 36 AD
he was sent north by the high priest of Jerusalem to arrest the followers of Jesus and
destroy their burgeoning heresy. As
Acts 9
describes, Paul was initially no Saint:
“breathing threats and murder against the disciples of the Lord,” he left in active
pursuit of “any belonging to the Way, men or women, [so] he might bring them
bound to Jerusalem.”
877
While crossing the Jordan Valley en route to Damascus, he
was struck by a vision that forever transformed him. Outside the city’s borders,
“suddenly a light from heaven flashed about him. And he fell to the ground and
heard a voice saying to him, ‘Saul, Saul, why do you persecute me?’”
878
Overwhelmed by the voice of God, Paul collapsed. When he arose “and when his
eyes were opened, he could see nothing.”
879
The would-be scourge of Christianity
was rendered helpless, led to Damascus by his company.
As the Bible tells, “for three days he was without sight, and neither ate nor
drank.”
880
On the final day Paul exhibited the first sign of faith (prayer) and was
subsequently healed by the Christian disciple Ananias. Ananias had already “heard
from many about this man [Paul], how much evil he has done to thy saints at
Jerusalem” acting under the “authority from the chief priests to bind all who call upon
thy name.”
881
He relayed this to God in a vision, yet the Lord was undeterred: “Go
876
Paul was born in Tarsus, a provincial capital of the Roman Empire.
877
Acts
9:1-2.
878
Acts
9:3-4.
879
Acts
9:8.
880
Acts
9:9.
881
Acts
9:13-14.
258
[to cure him], for he is a chosen instrument of mine to carry my name before the
Gentiles and kings and the sons of Israel; for I will show him how much he must
suffer for the sake of my name.”
882
It was under these conditions—a solemn mixture of divine mercy and
imposed suffering—that Ananias visited Paul with the gift of redemption. After
receiving the disciple’s touch, scales fell from Paul’s eyes, his blindness was cured,
and he rose to be baptized, dedicating his life to spreading the gospel that Jesus was
the son of God. As Ronald Brownrigg observes, “Paul’s conversion was remarkable
for the
total
reversal that it involved in his thinking, and the complete redirection of
his whole life.”
883
He was reborn as an Apostle in the very act of persecuting those to
whom he was now entrusted to serve.
Parallels between the conversions of Paul and Rousseau range from the
superficial (both were on a road) to the substantive. In each, supernatural epiphany
inspired radical redirection in the form of an individual calling. For both men, faith
was the gift bestowed upon them after physical trials, and the catalyst to their
redemption. Furthermore, neither appeared to have much
choice
in the matter;
illumination was the result of divine intervention rather than an autonomous act of
will.
884
And finally, both felt compelled to spread their newfound truths no matter the
consequences.
885
882
Acts
9:15-16.
-
883
Ronald Brownrigg,
Who’s Who in the New Testament
. (London: Routledge, 1995), p. 193.
884
Readers should recall that passivity—specifically, abandoning oneself to God—is a definitive
element of Christian conversion. For the prominence of passivity within Rousseau’s life and works,
readers should consult Starobinski’s
Transparency and Obstruction
.
885
Paul enraged his former allies in preaching Christianity, just as Rousseau alienated the
philosophes
in praising religiosity. See, for example, Voltaire’s quip (following the
Letter to d’Alembert
) that
Rousseau had perhaps “become a priest of the Church” in Besterman,
Voltaire's Correspondence
.
XIX.D7864.
259
This latter point proved particularly significant to Rousseau’s life. As with
Paul on the road to Damascus, he emerged from the road to Vincennes determined to
share his revelation. As he confides,
if I had ever been able to write a quarter of what I saw and felt under
that tree, how clearly I would have made all the contradictions of the
social system seem, with what simplicity I would have demonstrated
that
man
is naturally good and that it is from these institutions alone
that
men
become wicked. Everything that I was able to retain of these
crowds of great truths which illuminated me under that tree in a
quarter of an hour has been weakly scattered about in my three
principal writings.
886
Here, finally, is the source of Rousseau’s manifold claims of consistency and
coherence. Every discourse, treatise, novel and letter to escape his pen was an
attempt to articulate these compelling “truths.” More specifically, the most powerful
truth of all—the source of human suffering—had suddenly become clear: man was
“naturally good,” a victim of society’s perverting influence. Buoyed by its simplicity,
Jean-Jacques dedicated his remaining years to articulating this illumination,
struggling to convince his peers that they should heed his insights and reform their
religious, social and political institutions accordingly.
“That is how when I was thinking about it least,” Rousseau confides, “I
became an author almost in spite of myself.”
887
After all, his epiphany offered
rapturous clarity, but it also pressed him to pursue a life not of his making. From that
point forward Jean-Jacques “wanted to be consistent and shake the heavy yoke of
opinion from my shoulders once and for all” by relating his message of natural
886
Rousseau is here referring to the two
Discourses
and
Emile
, works which “are inseparable and
together form the same whole.”
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.575; OC I.1135-1136. (My emphasis,
to again underscore the distinction between
man
and
men
central to Rousseau’s concept of innocence.)
887
Although Rousseau cherishes freedom and liberty, he implies that he is prone to inactivity in the
absence of exogenous pressure. In addition, he confides that “I have always written in a cowardly
manner and badly when I was not strongly persuaded.”
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.575-576; OC
I.1136.
260
innocence and artificial corruption.
888
Yet this duty was, at best, a mixed blessing.
889
The individual sacrifice required to spread these contentious truths caused him
significant regret, and left him once again longing for solitude. Convinced that “great
tests” and “experience” demonstrated “the state in which I have put myself
890
is the
only one in which man can live as good and happy, since it is the most independent of
all, and the only one in which one never finds oneself in the necessity of harming
someone else for one’s own advantage,” he still dreamt of an “isolated and
independent” life free of social constraints.
891
When the real world failed him, Rousseau did what devout Christians often
do: he looked beyond the material world. He stole moments of ecstasy in fits of
reverie. Only then could he enjoy “the whole universe, everything that is, everything
that can be, everything that is beautiful in the perceptible world, and that is
imaginable in the intellectual world.”
892
Retreating within his imagination, Rousseau
took delight in a rapturous embrace of
everything
, in communion with a magnificent
divine order free of society’s flaws. Although this “golden age” crafted in his mind
left him “tender to the point of tears,” he was still saddened by “the nothingness of
my chimeras” and, more deeply, the “inexplicable void in myself that nothing could
888
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.576; OC I.1136.
889
As Rousseau laments, soon after his revelation Diderot “exhorted me to give vent to my ideas and
to compete for the prize. I did so, and from that instant I was lost. All the rest of my life and
misfortunes was the inevitable effect of that instant aberration.” Jean-Jacques’ complaint (and
deflection of accountability) is, however, somewhat misleading. It was the force and clarity of his
illumination—
not
the cajoling of his friend—that, by his own description, compelled him to embark on
his career as an author and public intellectual.
The Confessions
. CW V.294-295; OC I.351.
890
Readers should note that Rousseau’s language here takes the possessive form (“the state in which I
have put myself”), implying an autonomy at odds with his more frequent descriptions of duty as an
exogenously-imposed burden.
891
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.576; OC I.1137.
892
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.577; OC I.1138-1139.
261
fill; a certain yearning of the heart toward another sort of enjoyment the idea of which
I did not have and the need for which I felt nonetheless.”
893
In seeking to fill this void Rousseau moved closer to God.
Soon I raised my ideas from the surface of the earth to all the beings of
nature, to the universal system of things, to the incomprehensible
being who embraces everything. Then with my mind lost in that
immensity, I did not think, I did not reason, I did not philosophize;
with a sort of sensual pleasure I felt myself weighed down with the
weight of that universe, with rapture I abandoned myself to the
confusion of these great ideas, I loved to lose myself in imagination in
space; confined within the limits of beings my heart found itself too
constrained, I was smothered in the universe, I would have wanted to
throw myself into the infinite. I believe that if I had unveiled all the
mysteries of nature, I would have felt myself to be in a less delightful
situation than that stupefying ecstasy to which my mind abandoned
itself without reserve, and which sometimes made me cry out in the
agitation of my raptures, “Oh great being! Oh great being,” without
being able to say or think anything more.
894
As in the later
Reveries
, Rousseau discovered “continuous delirium” in total and utter
abandonment: “abandoning myself to the impression of the objects but without
thinking, without imagining, without doing anything else but feeling the calm and the
happiness of my situation.”
895
Raising himself to “the incomprehensible being who
embraces everything,” he savored the experience of floating amidst an unfathomable
divine order while losing his faculties of speech and reasoning. As he admits, the all-
too-human limitations of his mind only enhanced his sense of thrill: had he “unveiled
all the mysteries of nature,” he would not have achieved the “stupefying ecstasy”
borne of abandonment “without reserve.”
These moments of spiritual bliss were nonetheless fleeting. Rousseau’s
rapture could not quell his real-world misgivings; they rather made him long for a
893
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V.578-579; OC I.1140.
894
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V. 579; OC I.1141.
895
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V. 579; OC I.1141.
262
more immediate salvation. “[T]he trial I have made of these sweet enjoyments no
longer serves for anything but making me wait with less fright for the moment of
tasting them without distraction,” he lamented.
896
Compelled to serve the society of
men, Rousseau increasingly dreamt of an afterlife when, freed from the chains of
society, he might finally delight in the heavens.
Still, if Jean-Jacques’ faith in a beneficent Creator drew him closer to God it
also ushered his involvement in the world of men. After all, the means (and
correlative obligation) to enact corporeal salvation suddenly became clear on the road
to Vincennes. This combination of insight and prerogative reunited our self-
described misanthrope with a world he was now determined to change. Indeed,
Rousseau confides, on that day “I saw another universe and I became another man.”
More than simply affirm the existence of a divine order, his illumination gave him
new
life
, one defined by faith in humankind’s potential for virtuous redemption, and
the duty to encourage this promise in practice. The society of men might never exude
divine calm, but man
could
struggle to legitimize our interdependent chains, to
reawaken our conscience, hone our judgment, shun divisive, oppressive opinion and
align (as closely as possible) our associations with God’s harmonious order.
897
To save ourselves we might—indeed
must
—follow our Creator’s lead. After
Vincennes, Rousseau felt compelled to teach this lesson by example, to present
himself as a natural, uncorrupted man, a beacon of hope in a denatured world.
898
His
896
Letters to Malesherbes
. CW V. 580; OC I.1142.
897
Rousseau’s argument that man should embrace divine order (even though we can never replicate it
in society) parallels his claim that we should evoke natural goodness as a basis for reform (even though
we cannot return to our natural state). See:
Letter from Rousseau to Voltaire
, September 10, 1755.
CW III.105; OC III.226.
898
Although Rousseau was deeply discomforted by his newfound role, he struggled onwards. He
attributed his sense of duty to his secular attachments. “I have a very loving heart,” he confided. “I
263
illumination lighted the path to future redemption, one guided by a clear conviction
that humankind had disserved its God-given potential. But divine inspiration also
instilled within him a broad sense of civic duty, a desire to correct society’s failings
for the good of his species. It was thus on the road to Vincennes that Rousseau the
pious (felled by a revelation) and Rousseau the profane (champion of secular welfare)
became one. The dialectic between secular and spiritual themes that mingles so
awkwardly throughout his works was, during his shining epiphany, made painfully,
blissfully, harmoniously clear to him. It was that unprecedented moment of
coherence that Rousseau spent his remaining years struggling to relate, a flash of
divine inspiration that pressed him into corporeal service.
* * * * *
Following Vincennes, religious conviction imbued Rousseau with hope for his
species and a passion to better his world. Still, in
others
the very same sentiment
gave him serious pause. Religion may have been necessary, both to his own work
and the prosperity of his species, but religious practice often undermined the
requisites of civic virtue. Rather than encourage civil harmony, fanatical creeds bred
divisiveness and intolerance. Men were beholden to a single deity and shared a
common welfare, yet dogmatists obscured this truth by imposing artificial sectarian
differences. Far from justifying the need to reconcile religious and political
love men too much… I love them all, and it is because I love them that I hate injustice; it is because I
love them that I flee them, I suffer less from their evils when I do not see them.”
Letters to
Malesherbes
. CW V. 581; OC I.1144.
264
institutions, Rousseau’s assessment implied that such a relationship was nothing short
of fatal.
Machiavelli expressed a similar ambivalence in his
Discourses on Livy
. In an
aptly-named chapter,
How Important It Is to Take Account of Religion, and How
Italy, Lacking in Religion Thanks to the Roman Church, Has Been Ruined
, he
described Catholicism as a threat to civic republicanism: “the church has kept and
still keeps this land divided.”
899
Yet moments prior he argued that “there can be no
greater indication of the ruin of a state than to see a disregard for its divine
worship.”
900
And in the preceding section,
On the Religion of the Romans
, he insisted
that “[j]ust as the observance of divine worship is the cause of the greatness of
republics, so the disregard of divine worship is the cause of their ruin.” Although
“divine worship” was crucial to a polity’s prosperity, the most powerful house of
worship—the Catholic church—had “divided” Italy.
Like Rousseau in
On Civil Religion
, Machiavelli here seemed to lead readers
towards conflicting conclusions. Yet if both thinkers agreed upon the virtues of
religious piety
and
maintained the dangers of religious practice (in both cases, Roman
Catholicism), what are we to make of religion’s practical value? Does religiosity
threaten—rather than cultivate—political virtue and civic republicanism? Is it more
divisive than unifying? Given such compelling evidence to the contrary, do religious
associations serve
any
positive function in the composition and preservation of a
prosperous civil society?
899
Machiavelli,
Discourses on Livy
, I.12, p. 55.
900
Ibid., I.12, p. 53.
265
Perhaps more emphatically than Machiavelli,
901
Rousseau insisted that despite
the crimes of clerics, religion
was
necessary to strong democratic reform.
Furthermore, he claimed that
his
religious model was different from the dogmatic
creeds he so loathed, because it both facilitated civic virtue and safeguarded citizens
against sectarianism’s dangers. Simply put, where Catholicism failed so miserably—
where it divided and conquered rather than united and supported—his Civil Religion
would prosper. Yet what made Rousseau’s creed any different? Given the historical
failings of formal religions, why was
his
compatible with civic republicanism?
Conversely, if Rousseau was truly reborn following his conversion on the road to
Vincennes, why was he concerned at all? Why did he not simply abandon himself to
the overwhelming pleasure of reverie? Why not take solace in a dream of divine
redemption, while letting the world stay its own sel- destructive course?
In the end, Rousseau was unable to abandon his faith in either man or God;
the failings of dogmatic associations only pressed him to present an alternative, an
inclusive model of religious practice that adhered to both core Christian beliefs and
civic standards of tolerance and equality under law. In so doing, Civil Religion
affirmed what Rousseau had argued elsewhere, both before and after
The Social
Contract
: namely, that a truly civic religion engendered democratic virtue. As he
eulogized in
To the Republic of Geneva
, the prefatory dedication to the
Second
Discourse
, his birthplace was such an “edifying example of… a perfect union
between a Society of Theologians and of Men of Letters.”
902
He attributed the city’s
901
Although Machiavelli’s
Discourses
lauded religion’s role in facilitating civic republican virtue,
many read his
Prince
quite differently: as a cynical
realpolitik
manifesto in which successful
leadership requires machination, self-interest and savvy, rather than humbling, unifying faith.
902
Second Discourse
. CW III.9-10; OC III.119.
266
“saintliness of morals, severity of oneself and gentleness to others” to “the spirit of
Christianity” embodied by its pastors. In the
Letter to d’Alembert
, Genevan virtue
was credited to a
mélange
of religious piety, patriotic love, and culturally reified
morals.
903
In
Emile
, Christianity quelled revolutions and solidified the authority of
“modern governments,” while the Islamic “Turks, who have innumerable pious
institutions” were deemed “hospitable from religious principle.”
904
And in
Letters
Written From the Mountain
, idyllic Swiss communities were characterized not only
by striking landscapes, common heritage and familial arrangements, but also the
fortitude born of religious practice.
905
Religion offered a crucial foundation for civic
prosperity because it bound us to our fellow citizens, and urged us to work together
(no matter our particular differences) for the general welfare of all.
Still, Rousseau’s recourse to divine redemption—particularly in his later
works—smacked of personal neediness. His religiosity increasingly bore the marks
of a man obsessed with his own, rather than society’s, redemption. As the
Reveries
made plain, his time on earth was beset by turmoil and misunderstanding. When men
had failed to appreciate (or even accurately grasp) his position, he found himself
looking towards the heavens, insisting that God saw what his peers did not: the utility
of his thought, his innocence as an author and individual, and the pious lessons he
presented to a world increasingly ruled by
amour-propre
and perverse opinion. Yet
ultimately, religiosity united Rousseau with his fellows as much as with God. As he
admitted in a 1762 letter to the minister Frédéric-Guillaume de Montmollin,
903
Letter to d’Alembert
. CW X.322; OC V.88-89.
904
Emile
. E 313n.
905
Letters Written From the Mountain
(Second Letter). CW IX.154-155; OC III.712. See also:
The
Social Contract
. CW IV.222; OC III.468.
267
membership in the Christian
906
community gave him unabashed joy: “It is consoling
and sweet for me to be counted among its members, to participate in the public
worship they offer to the divinity, and to say to myself in their midst: I am with my
brothers.”
907
Fellowship, communion, harmony, connectedness
in this world
: as much as
anything, this was the indisputable promise of religion, to unite denatured creatures,
not in some distant postmortem realm, but during
this
lifetime and on
this
earth. That
is why, on no uncertain terms, religiosity was necessary to Rousseau’s thought. Only
religion could serve the greatest of all political needs—cultivating civic virtue—
because only religion reminded us that we were all creatures beholden to the same
Creator and the same divine order, no matter our denominational, national, ethnic,
and philosophical differences.
Writing about a “universal and all-pervading [divine] Spirit of Truth” in his
autobiography, Gandhi argued that “a man who aspires after that cannot afford to
keep out of any field of life. That is why my devotion to Truth has drawn me into the
field of politics; and I can say without the slightest hesitation, and yet in all humility,
that those who say that religion has nothing to do with politics do not know what
religion means.”
908
Rousseau could not have agreed more. In the final analysis, his
peculiar faith in man and God alike imbued with him the same stubborn conviction.
906
Again, we must emphasize the fact that by “Christian” Rousseau clearly means “Protestant,” and
not “Catholic.” He was, he explained to Beaumont, “fortunate to be born into the most reasonable and
holy Religion on earth, I remain inviolably attached to the worship of my Fathers. Like them, I take
Scripture and reason for the unique rules of my belief. Like them, I challenge the authority of men and
agree to submit to their formulas only to the extent I perceive their truth. Like them, I join in my heart
with the true servants of Jesus Christ and the true adorers of God, to offer him the homages of his
Church in the communion of the faithful.”
Letter to Beaumont
. CW IX.47; OC IV.960.
907
CC XII.2108.
908
Mohandas K. Gandhi,
An Autobiography: The Story of My Experiments With Truth
, Mahadev
Desai, tr. (Boston: Beacon Press, 1957 & 1993), p. 504.
268
The relationship between spirituality and secularism that others dismissed as
paradoxical, inconsistent, heretical, or even incoherent, Rousseau believed was true
and necessary to send us down a more virtuous path. The urgent necessity with
which he wrote, with which he engaged a world that so discomforted him, with which
he proclaimed his species’ innocence despite overwhelming evidence to the contrary,
suggests nothing less.
269
Bibliography
Allison, John M.S.
Lamoignon de Malesherbes: Defender and Reformer of the
French Monarchy, 1721-1794.
New Haven: Yale University Press, 1938.
Aristophanes.
Four Plays
, trans. William Arrowsmith, Richard Lattimore and
Douglass Parker. New York: Meridian, 1994.
Athanasius.
The Life of Antony and the Letter to Marcellinus
, trans. Robert C. Gregg.
Mahwah, NJ: Paulist Press, 1980.
Cobban, Alfred.
Rousseau and the Modern State
. London: G. Allen & Unwin Ltd.,
1934.
Augustine.
Confessions
, trans. Henry Chadwick. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1991.
________.
Letters
,
Volume V (204-270)
, trans. Sister Wilfrid Parsons. New York:
Fathers of the Church, Inc., 1956.
________.
Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers of the Christian Church: Volume V
,
trans. Benjamin B. Warfield. Grand Rapids, MI: Wm. B. Eerdmans
Publishing Company, 1971.
Barber, Benjamin R. “How Swiss is Rousseau?”
Political Theory
, vol. 13, no. 4,
November 1985.
Berlin, Isaiah.
Four Essays on Liberty
. New York: Oxford University Press, 1969.
Boss, Ronald Ian. “Rousseau’s Civil Religion and the Meaning of Belief: An Answer
to Bayle’s Paradox.”
Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth-Century
84,
1971.
Branham, R. Bracht and Marie-Odile Goulet-Cazé, eds.
The Cynics: The Cynic
Movement in Antiquity and Its Legacy
. Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1996.
Brown, Peter.
Religion and Society in the Age of Saint Augustine
. London: Faber
and Faber, 1972.
Brownrigg, Ronald.
Who’s Who in the New Testament
. London: Routledge, 1995.
270
Burgelin, Pierre.
Jean-Jacques Rousseau et la religion de Genève
. Geneva: Éditions
Labor et Fides, 1962.
Calvin, John.
On God and Political Duty, Second Revised Edition
, trans. John Allen
and Benjamin B. Warfield. (New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc.,
1956)
________.
Institutes of the Christian Religion in Two Volumes
, trans. Ford Lewis
Battles. Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1960.
Cassirer, Ernst.
The Philosophy of the Enlightenment
, trans. Fritz C. A. Koelln and
James P. Pettegrove. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1951.
Cranston, Maurice.
Jean-Jacques: The Early Life and Work of Jean-Jacques
Rousseau
, 1712-1754. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1982.
________.
The Noble Savage: Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 1754-1762
. Chicago: The
University of Chicago Press, 1991.
________.
The Solitary Self: Jean-Jacques Rousseau in Exile and Adversity
.
Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1997.
Crocker, Lester G.
Jean-Jacques Rousseau
,
Volume II
. New York: Macmillan
Publishers, 1963.
________.
Rousseau’s Social Contract
. Cleveland: Press of Case Western Reserve
University, 1968.
Cuendet, William.
La Philosophie religieuse de Jean-Jacques Rousseau et ses
sources
. Geneva: A. Jullien, 1913.
Darnton, Robert.
The Great Cat Massacre and Other Episodes in French Cultural
History
. New York: Basic Books, 1983.
________.
The Forbidden Best-Sellers of Pre-Revolutionary France
. New York: W.
W. Norton & Company, 1995.
de Bruyn, Theodore.
Pelagius’s Commentary on St. Paul’s Epistle to the Romans
.
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993.
Dérathe, Robert. “Jean-Jacques Rousseau et le Christianisme.”
Revue de
Métaphysique et de Morale
, 1948.
________.
Le rationalisme de Jean-Jacques Rousseau
. Paris: Presses Universitaires
de France, 1948.
271
Derrida, Jacques.
Of Grammatology
, trans. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak. Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1974.
Descartes, René.
Meditations on First Philosophy
,
Revised Edition
, trans. John
Cottingham. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Dewey, John.
The Public and Its Problems
. Athens, Ohio: Swallow Press/Ohio
University Press, 1954.
Diderot.
Encyclopédie, ou Dictionnaire Raisonné des Sciences, des Arts, et des
Métiers, par une société de gens de lettres, première édition de 1751-1780
.
Neuchâtel: Chez Samuel Faulche & Compagnie, 1765.
________.
Œuvres
,
Tome IV: Esthétique – Théâtre
, ed. Laurent Versini. Pari:
Éditions Robert Laffont, S.A., 1996.
Donaldson, Peter S.
Machiavelli and the Mystery of State
. New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1988.
Duffy, Edward.
Rousseau in England: The Context for Shelley’s Critique of the
Enlightenment
. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1979.
Evans, Robert F.,
Pelagius: Inquiries and Reappraisals
. (New York: The Seabury
Press, 1968)
Foucault, Michel.
Discipline & Punish: The Birth of the Prison
, trans. Alan Sheridan.
New York: Random House, 1979.
________.
The History of Sexuality, Volume I: An Introduction
, trans. Robert Hurley.
New York: Random House, 1978.
Françon, Marcel. “La condamnation de ‘l’Émile.’”
Annales de la Société Jean-
Jacques Rousseau
, tome 31, 1946-1949.
Furetière, Antoine.
Dictionnaire Universel
. The Hague and Rotterdam: Chez Arnout
& Reinier Leers, 1690.
Gagnebin, Bernard. “L’Étrange accueil fait aux ‘Confessions’ de Rousseau au XVIII
Siècle.”
Annales de la Société Jean-Jacques Rousseau
, tome 38, 1969-1971.
Galston, William A.
Liberal Pluralism: The Implications of Value Pluralism for
Political Theory and Practice
. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2002.
Gandhi, Mohandas K.
An Autobiography: The Story of My Experiments With Truth
,
trans. Mahadev Desai. Boston: Beacon Press, 1957.
272
Gossman, Lionel. “The Innocent Art of Confession and Reverie.”
Daedalus
, vol. 7,
no. 103, 1978.
Gouhier, Henri Gaston.
Les méditations métaphysiques de Jean-Jacques Rousseau
.
Paris: J. Vrin, 1970.
Grimsley, Ronald.
Rousseau and the Religious Quest
. London: Oxford University
Press, 1968.
Hadot, Pierre.
Philosophy as a Way of Life
, trans. Michael Chase. Oxford: Blackwell
Publishers Ltd., 1995.
Hartle, Ann.
The Modern Self in Rousseau’s Confessions: A Reply to Saint
Augustine
. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983.
Hobbes, Thomas.
Leviathan
,
Revised Edition
, ed. Richard Tuck. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1996.
________.
On the Citizen
, trans. Richard Tuck and Michael Silverthorne.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
________.
The Questions Concerning Liberty, Necessity, and Chance
. London:
Printed for Andrew Crook, 1656.
Huizinga, J.H.
Rousseau: The Self Made Saint
. New York: Viking Press, 1976.
Inge, William Ralph.
Christian Ethics and Modern Problems
. New York: The
Knickerbocker Press, 1930.
James, William.
The Varieties of Religious Experience
, ed. Martin E. Marty. New
York: Penguin Books, 1982.
Jaspers, Karl.
Socrates, Buddha, Confucius, Jesus: The Paradigmatic Individuals
,
trans. Ralph Manheim and ed. Hannah Arendt. New York: Harcourt Brace
Jovanovich, 1962.
Jerome.
Dogmatic and Polemical Works
, trans. John N. Hritzu. Washington, DC:
The Catholic University of America Press, 1965.
Jordan, David P.
The Revolutionary Career of Maximilien Robespierre
. Chicago:
The University of Chicago Press, 1985.
Juvenal.
The Satires
, trans. Niall Rudd. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991.
Kant, Immanuel.
Political Writings
,
Second Enlarged Edition
, ed. Hans Reiss and
trans. H.B. Nisbet. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.
273
Kelly, Christopher.
Rousseau’s Exemplary Life: The “Confessions” as Political
Philosophy
. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1987.
Kierkegaard, Søren.
The Journals
, trans. Alexander Dru. New York: Oxford
University Press, 1938.
Laertius, Diogenes.
Lives of Eminent Philosophers: Volume II
, trans. R.D. Hicks.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1925.
Lange, Lynda, ed.
Feminist Interpretations of Jean-Jacques Rousseau
. University
Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 2002.
Lejeune, Philippe.
L’autobiographie en France
,
Deuxième Édition
. Paris: Armand
Colin, 1998.
Lemaître, Jules.
Jean-Jacques Rousseau
. New York: The McClure Company, 1907.
Lowith, Karl.
Meaning in History
. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1949.
Leibniz, G. W.,
Theodicy: Essays on the Goodness of God
,
the Freedom of Man
,
and
the Origin of Evil
, trans. E.M. Huggard. La Salle, IL: Open Court Publishing
Company, 1985.
Locke, John.
A Letter Concerning Toleration
. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books,
1990.
Long, A.A.
Hellenistic Philosophy
,
Second Edition
. Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1986.
Luther, Martin.
Selections from His Writings
, trans. John Dillenberger. New York:
Anchor Books, 1961.
Machiavelli, Niccolò.
Discourses on Livy
, trans. Julia Conaway Bondanella and
Peter Bondanella. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997.
MacPherson, C.B.
The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to
Locke
. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1962.
Malebranche, Nicolas.
Philosophical Selections
, ed. Steven Nadler. Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1992.
Marable, Manning.
The Great Wells of Democracy: The Meaning of Race in
American Life
. New York: BasicCivitas Books, 2002.
Masson, Pierre-Maurice.
“La profession de foi du Vicaire Savoyard” de Jean-
Jacques Rousseau
,
édition critique
. Fribourg-Paris, 1914.
274
________.
La Religion de J. J. Rousseau: Vols. I-III
. Paris: Librairie Hachette, 1916.
Mauriac, François.
Trois grands hommes devant Dieu
. Paris: Editions du capitale,
1930.
McMahon, Darrin M.
Enemies of the Enlightenment: The French Counter-
Enlightenment and the Making of Modernity
. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2001.
Melzer, Arthur M.
The Natural Goodness of Man: On the System of Rousseau’s
Thought
. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1990.
Miller, James.
Rousseau: Dreamer of Democracy
. New Haven: Yale University
Press, 1984.
Mitchell, Joshua.
Not By Reason Alone: Religion, History and Identity in Early
Modern Political Thought
. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1993.
Montaigne, Michel de.
The Complete Essays
, trans. Donald M. Frame. Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 1958.
Montesquieu.
The Spirit of the Laws
, trans. and eds. Anne M. Cohler, Basia Carolyn
Miller and Harold Samuel Stone. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1989.
Nietzsche, Friedrich.
The Gay Science
, trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York:
Random House, Inc., 1974.
________.
On the Genealogy of Morals and Ecce Homo
, trans. Walter Kaufmann
and R.J. Hollingdale. New York: Random House, 1967.
________.
The Portable Nietzsche
, trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York: The Viking
Press, 1954.
Nozick, Robert.
Anarchy, State, and Utopia
. New York: Basic Books, Inc., 1974.
Nussbaum, Martha C.
The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic
Ethics
. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994.
Plato.
The Last Days of Socrates
, trans. Hugh Tredennick. New York: Penguin
Books, 1969.
________.
Laws
, trans. R.G. Bury. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1926.
________.
The Laws of Plato
, trans. Thomas L. Pangle. Chicago: The University of
Chicago Press, 1988.
275
________.
Phaedrus and the Seventh and Eighth Letters
, trans. Walter Hamilton.
New York: Penguin Books, 1973.
________.
Protagoras and Meno
, trans. W.K.C. Guthrie. New York: Penguin
Books, 1956.
________.
The Republic of Plato
,
Second Edition
, trans. Allan Bloom. New York:
Basic Books, 1968.
Plutarch.
Moralia: Volume XIII, Part II
, trans. Harold Cherniss. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1976.
Poulet, Georges.
Studies in Human Time
, trans. Elliott Coleman. New York: The
Johns Hopkins Press, 1956.
Py, Gilbert. “Jean-Jacques Rousseau et la Congrégation des Prêtres de l’Oratoire de
Jésus.”
Annales de la Société Jean-Jacques Rousseau
, tome 38, 1969-1971.
Quinet, Edgar.
Histoire de mes idées
. Paris: Flammarion, 1972.
Rees, B.R..
The Letters of Pelagius and His Followers
. Suffolk: The Boydell Press,
1991.
________.
Pelagius: A Reluctant Heretic
. Suffolk: The Boydell Press, 1988.
Riley, Patrick, ed.
The Cambridge Companion to Rousseau
. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2001.
________.
The General Will Before Rousseau: The Transformation of the Divine
into the Civic
. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986.
Rosenblatt, Helena.
Rousseau and Geneva: From the First discourse to the Social
Contract
,
1749-1762
. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
Séschelles, Hérault de.
Voyage à Montbard
. Paris: 1800.
Shklar, Judith N.
Men and Citizens: A Study of Rousseau’s Social Thought
.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969.
Shusterman, Richard.
Pragmatist Aesthetics: Living Beauty, Rethinking Art
. Oxford:
Blackwell, 1992.
Skinner, Quentin.
The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, Volume Two: The
Age of Reformation
. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978.
276
Sorell, Tom, ed.
The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes
. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1996.
Starobinski, Jean.
Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Transparency and Obstruction
, trans.
Arthur Goldhammer. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1988.
________.
Jean-Jacques Rousseau: La transparence et l’obstacle suivi de Sept
essais sur Rousseau
. Paris: Éditions Gallimard, 1971.
Strong, Tracy B.
Jean-Jacques Rousseau: The Politics of the Ordinary
,
New Edition
.
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 2002.
Taylor, Charles.
Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity
. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1989.
Talmon, J.L.
The Origins of Totalitarian Democracy
. London: Martin Secker &
Warburg, Ltd., 1952.
Thomas, Jacques-François.
Le Pélagianisme de J
.
-J
. Rousseau. Paris: Librairie
Nizet, 1956.
Tocqueville, Alexis de.
The Old Regime and the French Revolution
, trans. Stuart
Gilbert. New York: Anchor Books/Doubleday, 1955.
Trousson, Raymond and Frédéric S. Eigeldinger.
Dictionnaire de Jean-Jacques
Rousseau
. Paris: Honoré Champion Éditeur, 2001.
________.
Rousseau au jour le jour: Chronologie
. Pari: Honoré Champion Éditeur,
1998.
Voltaire.
Correspondenc
, ed. Theodore Besterman. Genève: Institut et Musée
Voltaire, 1953-1965.
________.
Lettres à M. de Voltaire sur La Nouvelle Héloïse
. Geneva, 1761.